Equality on What Basis? Evaluating Title IX’s Requirements in the Transgender Context

Seth Lucas
Volume 31
,  Issue 1

Introduction

Of the many federal statutes prohibiting sex discrimination,1See Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1791–96 (2020) (Alito, J., dissenting) (listing federal statutes that prohibit sex discrimination in various contexts). two have profoundly impacted women’s educational and career opportunities.2See, e.g., Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. 677, 685–88 (1973) (discussing Title VII’s enactment against the backdrop of historical and ongoing discrimination against women); Cannon v. Univ. of Chi., 441 U.S. 677, 694 n.16 (1979) (discussing hearings preceding Title IX’s adoption that highlighted ongoing discrimination against women in higher education). The first, Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, prohibits, among other things, sex discrimination in certain employment decisions.3Civil Rights Act of 1964, Pub. L. No. 88-352, tit. VII, § 703, 78 Stat. 241, 255–57 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. § 2000e-2); 42 U.S.C. § 2000e (defining “employer”). The second, Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, prohibits sex discrimination in federally funded education programs.4Education Amendments of 1972, Pub. L. No. 92-318, tit. IX, § 901(a), 86 Stat. 235, 373 (codified as amended at 20 U.S.C. § 1681(a)). But like the sexes, these two statutes are fundamentally different.5See United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S 515, 533 (1996) (“Physical differences between men and women, however, are enduring: ‘[T]he two sexes are not fungible . . . .’” (quoting Ballard v. United States, 329 U.S 187, 193 (1946))). Title VII bars covered employers from taking certain employment actions because an employee has particular traits, such as having the male or female sex.642 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a) (“It shall be an unlawful employment practice for an employer—(1) to fail or refuse to hire or to discharge any individual, or otherwise to discriminate against any individual with respect to his compensation, terms, conditions, or privileges of employment, because of such individual’s race, color, religion, sex, or national origin; or (2) to limit, segregate, or classify his employees or applicants for employment in any way which would deprive or tend to deprive any individual of employment opportunities or otherwise adversely affect his status as an employee, because of such individual’s race, color, religion, sex, or national origin.”); see Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1739. In contrast, Title IX, a condition for receiving federal aid, requires covered aid recipients to give each person equal educational opportunities regardless of the person’s sex.720 U.S.C. § 1681(a) (“No person in the United States shall, on the basis of sex, be excluded from participation in, be denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under any education program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance . . . .”); see, e.g., Davis v. Monroe Cnty. Bd. of Educ., 526 U.S. 629, 651 (1999) (requiring plaintiff to establish that sexual harassment “effectively denied equal access to an institution’s resources and opportunities” for the harassment to be actionable); Cannon, 441 U.S. at 704 n.36 (discussing legislative debates emphasizing equal opportunity); Cohen v. Brown Univ., 991 F.2d 888, 897 (1st Cir. 1993) (“Equal opportunity to participate lies at the core of Title IX’s purpose.”). But Title IX does not require sex-blind treatment. Title IX instead explicitly recognizes a person’s sex as relevant to participation in certain activities and access to certain physical spaces—such as with separate sports teams and locker rooms for boys and girls;8See Nondiscrimination on the Basis of Sex in Education Programs or Activities Receiving Federal Financial Assistance, 45 C.F.R. § 86.33, .41 (2022); Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972; a Policy Interpretation; Title IX and Intercollegiate Athletics, 44 Fed. Reg. 71399, 71413 (Dec. 11, 1979) (discussing the history of 1975 regulation). Congress twice recognized these regulations as a correct interpretation of Title IX’s requirements—including through legislation. See infra Part I. fraternities and sororities;920 U.S.C. § 1681(a)(6). and father-son or mother-daughter activities.10Id. § 1681(a)(8).

When Congress enacted Title VII and Title IX, Americans generally understood that “sex” refers to how a person’s body is organized for reproduction and that sex defines whether a person is male or female.11See infra Part I (examining the understanding of “sex” when Congress enacted Title VII and Title IX); infra Section III.A (restating the contemporary understanding of “sex”). But in recent years, the transgender movement challenged that understanding.12See generally Ryan T. Anderson, When Harry Became Sally: Responding to the Transgender Moment 78–85 (2019) (explaining the male-female sexual binary); Marybeth Herald, Transgender Theories and Court Practice, in Queer Mobilizations: LGBT Activists Confront the Law 187 (Scott Barclay, Mary Bernstein & Anna-Maria Marshall, eds., 2009) (explaining the transgender movement’s challenge to the male-female binary). The transgender movement claims that what a person is depends not on biology but instead on gender—a person’s inner “sense of being male, female, or something else.”13Anderson, supra note 12, at 30 (describing the transgender movement’s view that identity is rooted in something other than physical traits and is not limited to a male-female binary (quoting A Glossary: Defining Transgender Terms, Am. Psych. Ass’n (Sept. 2018), https://perma.cc/XW77-6L4P)); see Transgender Facts, Mayo Clinic, https://perma.cc/37D3-R3MZ; see also Carl R. Truman, The Rise and Triumph of the Modern Self 340 (2020) (“[T]o identify one’s gender by inner psychological conviction locates the LGBTQ+ within the world of expressive individualism and psychological man. Reality is inward and psychological, not outward and natural.”). It thus views biological traits like reproductive organs, chromosomes, or gamete production as having no ultimate bearing on whether a person is in fact male or female.14See Ally Windsor Howell, Transgender Persons and the Law 4 (2d ed. 2015) (“[A]mong the meanings we create are the meanings of . . . what body hair or long blond hair mean. In effect, gender is a language, a symbolic language . . . . Put another way, gender is a system of symbols and meanings . . . .” (quoting Nicole Ansonia, Gender Non-Conformists Under Title VII: A Confusing Jurisprudence in Need of a Legislative Remedy, 3 Geo. J. Gender L. 871, 875 (2003))); see also Yogyakarta Principles: Principles on the Application of International Human Rights Law in Relation to Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity 6 n.2 (Mar. 2007) [hereinafter Yogyakarta Principles], https://perma.cc/Y75Q-9P8L, (“Gender identity . . . refer[s] to each person’s deeply felt internal and individual experience of gender . . . including the personal sense of the body (which may involve, if freely chosen, modification of bodily appearance or function by medical, surgical, or other means) and other expressions of gender, including dress, speech and mannerisms.”).

In the transgender context, Title VII’s and Title IX’s protections consequently turn in part on the meaning of one three-letter word—”sex”—and its relationship to gender identity and transgender status.15The meaning of “sex” and its relationship to gender identity and transgender status is only part of the analysis. What the two statutes say about sex also matters. See Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1739 (2020) (“The question isn’t just what ‘sex’ meant, but what Title VII says about it.”). As this Comment argues, the text, contemporary understandings, and subsequent interpretations by an executive agency and Congress demonstrate that sex discrimination under Title IX means something very different than under Title VII. In 2020, for example, the Supreme Court concluded in Bostock v. Clayton County16140 S. Ct. 1731 (2020). that Title VII prohibits discrimination because of transgender status, even assuming that “sex” in Title VII refers to whether a person is biologically male or female.17Id. at 1737, 1739, 1741. The Court explained that transgender status arises from an incongruence between the person’s sex and gender identity, so an employer could not help but consider sex (albeit abstractly) by considering transgender status.18Id. at 1741–42.

But Title VII’s and Title IX’s protections also depend on what each statute says about sex.19See id. at 1739 (“The question isn’t just what ‘sex’ meant, but what Title VII says about it.”). Bostock declined to decide whether its reasoning applies to other statutes such as Title IX,20Id. at 1753 (“The employers worry that our decision will sweep beyond Title VII to other federal or state laws that prohibit sex discrimination. . . . But none of these other laws are before us . . . we do not prejudge any such question today.”). and rightly so. The text of Title IX, contemporary understandings, and subsequent early interpretations of Title IX by the executive branch and Congress all demonstrate that sex discrimination under Title IX means something very different than under Title VII. Like “[t]he two sexes,” Title VII and Title IX are simply “not fungible.”21See United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S 515, 533 (1996) (quoting Ballard v. United States, 329 U.S 187, 193 (1946)) (“Physical differences between men and women, however, are enduring: ‘[T]he two sexes are not fungible; a community made up exclusively of one [sex] is different from a community composed of both.’”).

Although the Supreme Court has yet to interpret Title IX’s requirements in the transgender context,22See West Virginia v. B.P.J., 143 S. Ct. 889, 889 (2023) (mem.) (Alito, J., dissenting from denial of application to vacate injunction) (observing that the Court declined to decide “whether either Title IX . . . or the Fourteenth Amendment’s Equal Protection Clause prohibits a State from restricting participation in women’s or girls’ sports based on genes or physiological or anatomical characteristics.”). three federal courts of appeals have.23A.C. v. Metro. Sch. Dist. of Martinsville, 75 F.4th 760, 764 (7th Cir. 2023), petition for cert. filed, No. 23-392 (Oct. 11, 2023); Adams ex rel. Kasper v. Sch. Bd. of St. Johns Cnty., 57 F.4th 791, 796 (11th Cir. 2022); Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 972 F.3d 586, 593 (4th Cir. 2020); Whitaker v. Kenosha Unified Sch. Dist. No. 1 Bd. of Educ., 858 F.3d 1034, 1038–39 (7th Cir. 2017). Other federal courts of appeals have also addressed this issue but did so either in dicta or without a substantial analysis. For instance, although the Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit denied a stay of a preliminary injunction in a private facilities case, it did not reach the merits. See Dodds v. U.S. Dept. of Educ., 845 F.3d 217, 221–22 (6th Cir. 2016). In another decision, Meriwether v. Hartop, the court explained only briefly that a professor’s refusal to use preferred pronouns did not amount to Title IX sexual harassment because the student was not effectively denied equal access to an educational program or activity. 992 F.3d 492, 511 (6th Cir. 2021). The Meriwether court focused the bulk of its analysis and decision on the professor’s free speech claim and addressed the sexual harassment claim within that context. See id. at 503–12. The Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit similarly observed that Bostock’s reasoning applies to section 1557 of the Affordable Care Act. Doe. v. Snyder, 28 F.4th 103, 113–14 (9th Cir. 2022). In June 2023, citing Doe v. Snyder and Grimm, the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit held that Title IX should be construed similarly to Title VII and applied Bostock’s holding regarding sexual orientation to a Title IX sexual harassment claim. See Grabowski v. Ariz. Bd. of Regents, 69 F.4th 1110, 1116 & n.1 (9th Cir. 2023) (citing Doe, 28 F.4th at 114). Again, however, the court did not address Title IX in the transgender context. See id. But the court will likely decide the question in the near future. See Order Granting Motion for Injunctive Relief, Roe v. Critchfield, No. 23-2807, slip op. at 1 (9th Cir. Oct. 27, 2023); see also Roe v. Critchfield, No. 23-cv-00315, 2023 WL 6690596, at *1, *15 (D. Idaho Oct. 12, 2023) (holding, inter alia that Title IX permits separate restroom facilities for each sex), appeal filed No. 23-2807 (Oct. 16, 2023). The Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit will also likely address the question again soon, this time regarding athletics. See B.P.J. v. W. Va. State Bd. of Educ., No. 22-1078, 2023 U.S. App. LEXIS 8379 (4th Cir. Feb. 22, 2023) (granting the student’s motion for a stay). And as of October 2023, a petition for certiorari is pending before the U.S. Supreme Court in Martinsville. Two of these courts concluded that Title IX requires federal funding recipients to treat a person consistent with that person’s gender identity.24Grimm, 972 F.3d at 593, 616–17 (applying Bostock); Whitaker, 858 F.3d at 1038–39; see also Martinsville, 75 F.4th at 764 (applying Whitaker and Bostock). Put another way, they determined that where sex and gender identity conflict, Title IX prohibits treating a person in a manner consistent with that person’s sex. Thus, if a student who has a male sex identifies as female, under these two decisions, Title IX requires treating that student as a female.

Those decisions misunderstood Title IX. Title IX does not impose such a requirement. And even if Bostock’s reasoning, which cannot be applied to Title IX, were applied, Title IX would still permit a federal aid recipient to treat a person in a manner consistent with that person’s sex regardless of whether the person has transgender status.25But see Martinsville, 75 F.4th at 769 (“Applying Bostock’s reasoning to Title IX, we have no trouble concluding that discrimination against transgender persons is sex discrimination for Title IX purposes, just as it is for Title VII purposes. As Bostock instructs, we ask whether our three plaintiffs are suffering negative consequences (for Title IX, lack of equal access to school programs) for behavior that is being tolerated in male students who are not transgender. Our decision in Whitaker followed this approach.” (citations omitted)). As this Comment explains, this understanding of Bostock and Title IX is incorrect. Part I of this Comment outlines the development and early interpretations of Title IX. Part II outlines Title VII’s and Title IX’s respective disparate treatment standards, the Supreme Court’s reasoning in Bostock interpreting Title VII, and the three federal courts of appeals’ reasoning in interpreting Title IX in the transgender context. Part III then explains that Title IX, as originally understood, permits treating a person as male or female based on that person’s immutable sex. Part IV explains that Bostock’s reasoning cannot be applied to Title IX because of the fundamental differences between Title VII and Title IX. Part IV also explains that even if the but-for test in Bostock were applied, Title IX would still permit treating a person as male or female based on that person’s sex. Because Congress in 2010 extended Title IX’s requirements to cover federally funded medical programs,26Patient Protection & Affordable Care Act, Pub. L. No. 111-148, tit. I, § 1557, 124 Stat. 260 (2010) (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 18116) (incorporating Title IX’s nondiscrimination requirements to apply in “any health program or activity”). Part V examines the implications of an original understanding of Title IX for insurance coverage and medical treatments in the transgender context.

As an initial matter, this Comment does not address the proper policy approach to questions surrounding gender identity and transgender status. It recognizes, however, that such questions are sensitive and controversial,27See Janus v. Am. Fed’n of State, Cnty., & Mun. Emps., 138 S. Ct. 2448, 2476 (2018) (describing “gender identity” as one of several “sensitive political topics, and . . . [a] matter[ ] of profound ‘value and concern to the public.’” (quoting Snyder v. Phelps, 562 U.S. 443, 453 (2011))). and that the use of certain terms or definitions over others may appear to be a statement on those questions. Where this Comment uses such terms or definitions, it does so solely for clarity. That said, two terms can and should be defined. “Gender identity” refers to a person’s “internal sense of being male, female, or something else,” such as genderqueer, agender, or nonconforming.28A Glossary: Defining Transgender Terms, Am. Psych. Ass’n (Sept. 2018), https://perma.cc/XW77-6L4P); see Transgender Facts, supra note 13; Understanding the Transgender Community, Hum. Rts. Campaign, https://perma.cc/9PW9-CM45 (listing several gender identities). “Transgender status,” in turn, indicates that a person has a gender identity that differs from that person’s sex.29A Glossary: Defining Transgender Terms, supra note 28; Transgender Facts, supra note 13; Understanding the Transgender Community, supra note 28. Thus, for instance, a transgender female is a person whose sex is male but who identifies as a female.30See Transgender Facts, supra note 13; see also Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1741 (2020).

I.      Development and Early Interpretations of Title IX

The early twentieth century was marked by increasing women’s activism, resulting in the Nineteenth Amendment and greater numbers of women entering both the workforce and higher education.31Susan Cahn, Coming on Strong: Gender and Sexuality in Twentieth-Century Sports 7–9, 164–65, 181–84 (1994), reprinted in Equal Play: Title IX & Social Change 9 (Nancy Hogshead-Maker & Andrew Zimbalist eds., 2007). Although this activism ignited debates on everything from the vote to hemlines, women’s social roles did not change significantly for most of the century.32Id. at 9; Deborah L. Rhode, Justice and Gender: Sex Discrimination and the Law 29–34 (1989) (explaining that views on women and their roles remained largely unchanged from the 1920s to the 1960s). Indeed, even as women’s participation in the workforce rose significantly during the Second World War, American society largely retained longstanding views on women’s roles.33See id. But by the middle of the century, the feminist movement that brought about the Nineteenth Amendment was evolving.34See id. at 11–14, 34 (explaining early feminist efforts to achieve legal equality while not challenging “natural roles,” and noting that a “substantial” challenge to social roles did not arise until the 1960s); Anderson, supra note 12, at 150 (contrasting early feminist efforts to challenge the loss of women’s legal identity in marriage and obtain equal rights with men with mid-twentieth century feminist challenges to social roles). As the United States plunged into the second half of the twentieth century, a new wave of feminism began to challenge the idea that a woman’s body defined her role in society.35See Rhode, supra note 32, at 34; Anderson, supra note 12, at 150. A more ambitious wing of the movement went further, however, and argued that physical distinctions between men and women should be completely irrelevant.36See Anderson, supra note 12, at 151–52 (quoting Shulamith Firestone, The Dialectic of Sex 11 (Farrar, Straus & Giroux 2003) (1970)) (explaining Shulamith Firestone’s argument for replacing natural forms of procreation with artificial forms to make sex distinctions irrelevant).

Although this unlinking of the body from social roles would later have implications for social views on sex and gender,37See id. at 151–54; Kathleen Lennon, Feminist Perspectives on the Body, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Edward N. Zalta, ed. 2019), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminist-body/#Bib (noting connection between second wave feminism and the sex-gender dichotomy). in the 1960s and 1970s, biological distinctions were still viewed as fixed and defining whether a person is male or female. For instance, one 1966 article explained that “[t]he standard outcome in the biological development of the individual is a predominance of anatomical and physiological structures and functions that are the basis of either maleness or femaleness.”38Daniel G. Brown & David B. Lynn, Human Sexual Development: An Outline of Components and Concepts, 28 J. Marriage & Fam. 155, 156 (1966). Numerous dictionaries from that time echoed a similar understanding of sex as either male or female and defined by how a person’s body is reproductively organized.39See, e.g., Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1784–1791 (2020) (Alito, J., dissenting) (listing dictionary definitions of “sex” from dictionaries published throughout the twentieth century, including dictionaries from the years 1964, 1966, and 1969); Adams ex rel. Kasper v. Sch. Bd. of St. Johns Cnty., 57 F.4th 791, 812 (11th Cir. 2022) (listing definitions from dictionaries published between 1970 to 1980); Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 972 F.3d 586, 632–33 (4th Cir. 2020) (Niemeyer, J., dissenting) (listing definitions from dictionaries published between 1970 and 1980). Even Leo Kanowitz in his influential 1969 text, Women and the Law: The Unfinished Revolution, recognized “basic anatomical differences between male and female.”40Leo Kanowitz, Women and the Law: The Unfinished Revolution 18 (1969); see also Bob Egelko, Leo Kanowitz, Early Proponent of Women’s Rights, Dies at 81, SFGATE (Aug. 24, 2007), https://perma.cc/UA7P-XHUM.

Indeed, the feminist movement did not challenge the idea that men and women are biologically different.41See Mari Mikkola, Feminist Perspectives on Sex and Gender, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman, eds. 2022), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminism-gender/ (explaining that feminists viewed “sex” as defining whether a person is male or female). It instead challenged the perception of womanhood as understood in relation to social and domestic roles.42See Anderson, supra note 12, at 150–52 (outlining feminist thinkers’ views). But see Mikkola, supra note 41 (arguing that feminist thinker Simone de Beauvoir saw “sex” as existential rather than biological). Feminist Betty Friedan, for example, argued in 1963 that a woman’s “biological function” should not be interpreted to require a woman to be a mother and thus stifle any “goal,” “purpose,” or “ambition.”43See Anderson, supra note 12, at 150 (quoting Betty Friedan, The Feminine Mystique 462 (W.W. Norton & Co. reprt. ed. 2010) (1963)). And Shulamith Firestone, arguing that “the end goal” is a world where sex distinctions “would no longer matter culturally,” implicitly acknowledged that biological distinctions exist and define whether a person is male or female.44See id. at 151–52 (quoting Shulamith Firestone, The Dialectic of Sex 11 (Farrar, Sraus & Giroux 2003) (1970)) (describing Firestone’s view that women’s “seizure of control of reproduction” through “artificial reproduction” would give women “ownership of their bodies”).

In 1970, these social currents converged with greater federal involvement in education to spark conversations about sex discrimination in higher education.45See Deborah L. Brake, Getting in the Game: Title IX and the Women’s Sports Revolution 17 (2010) (“Title IX emerged from a broader social movement seeking the recognition and vindication of women’s rights.”); Education Amendments of 1972, 61 Geo. L.J. 1067, 1067–68 (1973) (discussing the development of federal involvement in higher education). That year, a special subcommittee of the House of Representatives’ Committee on Education held hearings on legislation that would make “sex” a protected classification in Title VI.46Discrimination Against Women: Hearing on Section 805 of H.R. 16098 Before the Special Subcomm. on Educ. of the H. Comm. on Educ. and Lab., Part 1, 91st Cong. (1970) [hereinafter 1970 Hearings, Part 1]; Cannon v. Univ. of Chi., 441 U.S. 667, 694 n.16 (1979). Title VI made nondiscrimination regarding race, color, and national origin a condition for receiving federal funds.47Civil Rights Act of 1964, Pub. L. 88-352, tit. VI, § 601, 78 Stat. 241, 252 (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 2000d). The bill sought to bar federal funding recipients from also engaging in sex discrimination.48Cannon, 441 U.S. at 694 n.16 (“H. R. 16098 . . . would simply have added the word ‘sex’ to the list of discriminations prohibited by § 601 of Title VI.”). During the hearings, “it became clear that educational institutions were the primary focus of complaints concerning sex discrimination.”49Id..; see, e.g., 1970 Hearings, Part 1, supra note 46, at 237–38 (statement of Dr. Ann Sutherland Harris, Assistant Professor of Art History at Columbia University, as spokeswomen for Columbia Women’s Liberation) (arguing that the amendment was needed to remedy discrimination against women in higher education); id. at 584 (statement of Diane Blank and Susan D. Ross, members of the Women’s Rights Committee of New York University Law School) (testifying “about certain discriminatory policies practiced by the law school against women members, especially in the area of admission and scholarship”); Discrimination Against Women: Hearing on Section 805 of H.R. 16098 Before the Special Subcomm. on Educ. of the H. Comm. on Educ. and Lab., Part 2, 91st Cong. 664 (1970) [hereinafter 1970 Hearings, Part 2] (statement of Frankie Freeman, Commissioner on the U.S. Commission on Civil Rights). But witnesses from the United States Justice Department and the Civil Rights Commission, while supporting the legislation’s general goal, raised concerns about its “significant public policy consequences.”501970 Hearings, Part 2, supra note 49, at 664 (statement of Frankie Freeman, Commissioner, U.S. Commission on Civil Rights); see id. at 677 (statement of Jerris Leonard, Assistant Attorney General, Civil Rights Division, Department of Justice) (“[W]e are not able to support this legislation in its present form . . . .”). Such consequences included denial of funding to single-sex institutions, elimination of sex-specific housing, denial of funding and government surplus to the Boy and Girl Scouts, and a dismantling of “bona fide distinctions” between men and women.511970 Hearings, Part 2, supra note 49, at 664. These and other witnesses proposed that Congress should instead adopt separate legislation that would “achieve . . . sexual equality without eradicating bona fide distinctions based on sex.”52Id.; see Cannon, 441 U.S. at 694 n.16 (noting proposal for separate provision parallel to but more limited than Title VI); see also 1970 Hearings Part 2, supra note 49, at 678 (proposing “separate legislation . . . which would prohibit discrimination on the ground of sex” but which “would make the prohibition inapplicable where sex is a bona fide basis for differential treatment”). The Civil Rights Commission proposed that the first section of such legislation should mirror Title VI but refer only to “sex.” Id. at 665 (statement of Frankie Freeman, Commissioner, U.S. Commission on Civil Rights). The second part of the proposal permitted “reasonable classification, separation or exclusion of persons on the basis of sex where such classification, separation or exclusion is based upon bona fide qualifications or standards of propriety which are not inconsistent with the purposes of this title.” Id. The second section thus sought to prevent “unreasonable” applications of the title, such as “integrating rest rooms and dormitories.” Id. The Justice Department’s proposal read as follows:

Sec. 2. (a) No person in the United States shall, on the ground of sex, be excluded from participation in, denied the benefits of, or subjected to discrimination under, any education program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance, except where sex is a bona fide ground for differential treatment.

. . . .

Sec. 6. For the purposes of this act, the term “education” includes pre-school, elementary, secondary and post-secondary education.

Id. at 690–91 (statement of Jerris Leonard). The language would have barred sex discrimination in, for instance, “availability of scholarships and fellowships; admission to graduate programs; and hiring, compensation, and promotion of faculty and staff members.” Id. at 678. It would have also exempted single-sex institutions as they “could satisfy the exception regarding bona fide distinctions.” 1970 Hearings, Part 2, supra note 49, at 678. And it would have permitted “separate dormitories and separate gymnasiums for men and women” while allowing regulating agencies to otherwise define the extent of the proviso “on the basis of particular situations which arise.” Id. The proposal “would not reach federally assisted programs outside the area of education.” Id.

The proposed legislation failed.53See Cannon, 441 U.S. at 694 n.16. But much of the language proposed in the hearings resurfaced in the House version of the Education Amendments of 1972.54Id.; compare 1970 Hearings, Part 2, supra note 49, at 665, 690–91 (detailing proposals for separate legislation) with Education Amendments of 1972, Pub. L. No. 92-318, tit. IX, § 901(a), 86 Stat. 235, 373–74 (codified as amended at 20 U.S.C. § 1681(a)). Like the original proposals, the new proposal was also framed as an amendment to Title VI.55Cannon, 441 U.S. at 694 n.16; see 117 Cong. Rec. 30155–76 (1971) (statement of Sen. Birch Bayh) (observing that “[t]he antidiscrimination provisions of the Civil Rights Act . . . do not deal with sex discrimination” and that “[w]e allow this gap in our civil rights laws to continue”); id. at 30407–08 (statement of Sen. Birch Bayh) (noting that “[t]his is identical language, specifically taken from title VI” and that “we really are not doing anything to the private school that is not now in the law under title VI . . . . We are only adding the 3-letter word ‘sex’ to existing law”). When the legislation emerged from the House Committee and then the Joint Committee, however, the language was moved into its own separate title, Title IX.56Education Amendments of 1972, Pub. L. No. 92-318, tit. IX, 86 Stat. 235 (codified as amended at 20 U.S.C. § 1681); Cannon, 441 U.S. at 694 n.16. Unlike the original proposals in 1970, the language did not include a general exemption for bona fide distinctions.57Compare 1970 Hearings, Part 2, supra note 49 at 678 (including exemption) with 20 U.S.C. § 1681 (omitting any general exemption for bona fide distinctions).

Title IX, in its advocates’ eyes, had two reciprocal goals.58Gebser v. Lago Vista Indep. Sch. Dist., 524 U.S. 274, 286 (1998) (citing Cannon, 441 U.S. at 704). First, Title IX aimed to increase opportunities for women to access and participate in higher education.59See id.; 117 Cong. Rec. 30155 (1971) (statement of Sen. Birch Bayh) (observing that the bill aimed to aid “victims of economic discrimination” and urging, “let us ensure that no American will be denied access to higher education because of . . . sex. Today, I am submitting an amendment . . . which will guarantee that women, too, enjoy the educational opportunity every American deserves”); see also N. Haven Bd. of Educ. v. Bell, 456 U.S. 512, 526–27 (1982) (treating Senator Bayh’s remarks as an authoritative statement of congressional intent). Second, it sought to prevent federal funding recipients from using tax dollars to bar women from educational opportunities.60See Gebser, 524 U.S. at 286 (citing Cannon, 441 U.S. at 704). Advocates emphasized that Title IX would do for sex what Title VI did for race in the context of federal funding.61117 Cong. Rec. 39256 (1971) (statement of Rep. Edith Green) (“It is really the same as the Civil Rights Act in terms of race.”); 117 Cong. Rec. 30407 (statement of Sen. Birch Bayh) (“This is identical language, specifically taken from title VI of the 1964 Civil Rights Act . . . .”); 117 Cong. Rec. 30155 (statement of Sen. Birch Bayh) (emphasizing equal opportunity for women); 117 Cong. Rec. 39251 (statement of Rep. Edith Green) (denying that bill requires quotas of women); 118 Cong. Rec. 18437–38 (1972) (statements of Sen. Birch Bayh, Rep. Edith Green, and Rep. Thomas Pell) (expressing objections to concerns that Title IX would require quotas). But unlike with the treatment of race, no one disputed that bona fide differences existed between the two sexes,62See 118 Cong. Rec. 5807 (statement of Sen. Birch Bayh) (“Under this amendment, each Federal agency which extends Federal financial assistance is empowered to issue implementing rules and regulations effective after approval of the President. These regulations would allow enforcing agencies to permit differential treatment by sex only—very unusual cases where such treatment is absolutely necessary to the success of the program—such as in classes for pregnant girls or emotionally disturbed students, in sports facilities or other instances where personal privacy must be preserved.”); 117 Cong. Rec. 39251 (statement of Rep. Edith Green) (“As I said before, it does not go as far as the equal rights amendment. I see no reason why anybody who supported the equal rights amendment should hesitate in the least to support title X as it is now written.”); see also 117 Cong. Rec. 35317 (statement of Rep. Charles Thone) (explaining that the Equal Rights Amendment “is not a unisex measure” and noting that under the ERA, “legislation and administrative actions may take into account a physical characteristic unique to one sex”); id. (statement of Rep. William Keating) (“This amendment makes clear that women are to be treated as equal human beings with men, but not as human beings identical to men in every respect.”); supra notes 50–52 and accompanying text. even if debate did exist at the time over the extent and implications of those differences.63See Brake, supra note 45, at 8–10 (discussing how Title IX reflected differing feminist views). No one, for instance, contested that the housing exemption undermined Title IX’s objectives.64See, e.g., 117 Cong. Rec. 39263 (statement of Rep. Edith Green) (raising “no objection” to the exemption). In 1974 and then again in 1976, Congress amended Title IX to clearly exempt various single-sex associations and programs from its nondiscrimination provision.65See S.J. Res. 40, 93d Cong. § 3(a), 88 Stat. 1862 (1974); Education Amendments of 1976, Pub. L. No. 94-482, § 412(a), 90 Stat. 2081, 2234 (codified as amended at 20 U.S.C. § 1681).

Moreover, shortly after Title IX’s adoption, Congress permitted the then-Department of Health, Education, and Welfare (“HEW”) to promulgate regulations that explicitly allowed separate sports programs for males and females.66Brake, supra note 45, at 18–21. Congress did not create a statutory exception from the nondiscrimination requirement for sports, however. When HEW began developing regulations addressing sports at Congress’s direction, it grappled with two conflicting policy positions.67Id. at 18–20. Some stakeholders urged the full integration of sports, even if gradually accomplished by temporarily allowing sex-specific teams.68Id. at 20–21. Other stakeholders, however, argued that separate but equal programs were necessary for women to develop and pursue their own opportunities.69Id. HEW chose the latter approach.70Id. at 21–22. And despite attempts in Congress to reject the final regulations, Congress allowed them to go into effect.71Id. at 21; Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972; a Policy Interpretation; Title IX and Intercollegiate Athletics, 44 Fed. Reg. 71399, 71413 (Dec. 11, 1979) (discussing the history of 1975 regulation). Some commenters on recent proposed changes to these rules have argued that by reviewing and accepting the 1975 rule and HEW’s 1979 interpretation, and then adopting the executive branch’s understanding of Title IX in the 1988 Civil Rights Restoration Act, Congress shut the door to further rulemaking on athletics without express legislative authorization. See Alliance Defending Freedom, Comment Letter on the Notice of Proposed Rulemaking on Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, at 4–5 (May 15, 2023), https://perma.cc/4R6E-ABWR; Sarah Parshall Perry, Comment Letter on the Notice of Proposed Rulemaking on Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, at 9–10 (May 15, 2023), https://perma.cc/7VVA-M242.

Under the final 1975 HEW athletic regulations, equal opportunity did not mean that women and men must be treated identically. Rather, equal opportunity required that “male and female athletes should receive equivalent treatment, benefits, and opportunities” and that “athletic interests and abilities of male and female students must be equally effectively accommodated.”72Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972; a Policy Interpretation; Title IX and Intercollegiate Athletics, 44 Fed. Reg. at 71414 (summarizing HEW’s policy interpretation of the 1975 regulation). The regulations required, for instance, housing and locker rooms provided on a sex-specific basis to be “comparable” in quality.73Nondiscrimination on the Basis of Sex in Education Programs and Activities Receiving or Benefiting from Federal Financial Assistance, 40 Fed. Reg. 24128, 24141 (June 4, 1975). Scholarships had to be available “substantially proportionate” to men’s and women’s “participation rates.”74Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972; a Policy Interpretation; Title IX and Intercollegiate Athletics, 44 Fed. Reg. at 71415; see 45 C.F.R. § 86.37. As HEW acknowledged in its 1979 interpretation, the regulations countenanced that “[s]ome aspects of athletic programs may not be equivalent for men and women because of unique aspects of particular sports or athletic activities.”75Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972; a Policy Interpretation; Title IX and Intercollegiate Athletics, 44 Fed. Reg. at 71415. As long as the unique needs of male and female students in each program were “met equivalently,” however, such differences were justifiable.76Id. at 71416. Again, “identical benefits, opportunities, or treatment [were] not required, provided the overall effect of any differences is negligible.”77Id. at 71415. Under the regulations, equality did not require ignoring biological differences.78See id.

Title IX and its early implementing regulations thus incorporated some feminist views while rejecting others.79See Brake, supra note 45, at 8 (discussing how Title IX reflects different strands of feminist legal theory). The statute and implementing regulations effectively made a woman’s body irrelevant to the educational opportunities that a woman could pursue. But it did not make physical distinctions between men and women entirely irrelevant as some feminists and groups urged.80See id. at 20 (discussing views regarding integrated sports). Title IX and its implementing regulations affirmed distinctions between the two sexes while ensuring that such distinctions are not the basis for unequal treatment that could limit opportunities for either sex. As HEW stated regarding athletics, Title IX requires “equal”—not “identical”—treatment.81Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972; a Policy Interpretation; Title IX and Intercollegiate Athletics, 44 Fed. Reg. at 71415.

II.      Title IX, Title VII, and Interpretations in the Transgender Context

A.      Title IX’s Disparate Treatment Standard

Shortly after Title IX’s adoption, the U.S. Supreme Court recognized a private right of action to enforce Title IX’s nondiscrimination requirements.82Cannon v. Univ. of Chi., 441 U.S. 677, 717 (1979). To establish a Title IX cause of action, a plaintiff must demonstrate exclusion from, denial of benefits of, or discrimination under an educational program that receives federal financial assistance, and that the discrimination occurred on the basis of the plaintiff’s sex.83Seamons v. Snow, 84 F.3d 1226, 1232 (10th Cir. 1996); see also G.G. ex rel. Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 822 F.3d 709, 718 (4th Cir. 2016) (“G.G. must allege (1) that he was excluded from participation in an education program because of his sex; (2) that the educational institution was receiving federal financial assistance at the time of his exclusion; and (3) that the improper discrimination caused G.G. harm.”), vacated and remanded, 580 U.S. 1168 (2017). That a person was merely treated differently on the basis of sex is insufficient in itself to establish Title IX liability.84See, e.g., Grabowski v. Ariz. Bd. of Regents, 69 F.4th 1110, 1113–14 (9th Cir. 2023) (affirming dismissal of harassment claim for “fail[ure] to allege a deprivation of educational opportunity”); Seamons, 84 F.3d at 1232 (reciting the elements of a Title IX cause of action). Liability can arise either from intentional discrimination or deliberate indifference to discrimination.85Poloceno v. Dall. Indep. Sch. Dist., 826 F. App’x. 359, 362 (5th Cir. 2020). For liability to arise from deliberate indifference, a plaintiff must also show that the defendant had “actual knowledge” of the discrimination and chose to not act.86See Gebser v. Lago Vista Indep. Sch. Dist., 524 U.S. 274, 289 (1998); see Doe v. Edgewood Indep. Sch. Dist., 964 F.3d 351, 358–59 (5th Cir. 2020) (applying Gebser to an employee-on-student harassment claim).

Generally, courts agree that Title IX prohibits only intentional discrimination—disparate treatment—but not disparate impact.87See, e.g., Jackson v. Birmingham Bd. of Educ., 544 U.S. 167, 173 (2005) (describing Title IX as a “prohibition on intentional sex discrimination”); Alexander v. Sandoval, 532 U.S. 275, 282 (2001) (observing that Cannon “created a private right of action to enforce [Title IX’s] ban on intentional discrimination”); Gebser, 524 U.S. at 290 (requiring that indifference to discrimination be “deliberate” and “an official decision” to be actionable under Title IX); Biediger v. Quinnipiac Univ., 691 F.3d 85, 97–98 (2d Cir. 2012) (recognizing that Title IX prohibits intentional discrimination); Poloceno, 826 F. App’x at 362 (rejecting disparate impact claim because Title IX prohibits “only intentional discrimination”). Although Title IX did not replicate Title VI, because Title IX was modeled on Title VI, courts have looked to how Title VI operates as informative when interpreting Title IX.88See Cannon v. Univ. of Chi., 441 U.S. 677, 699–701, 717 (looking to Title VI to find private right of action). Initially, federal courts of appeals split over whether Title IX permitted disparate impact claims because of disagreement over whether Title VI prohibited only intentional discrimination.89Doe v. Univ. of Denver, 952 F.3d 1182, 1193 n.8 (10th Cir. 2020) (noting early circuit split over disparate impact claim); see Fort v. Dallas Indep. Sch. Dist., No. 95-10323, 1996 U.S. App. LEXIS 44677, at *3 n.3 (5th Cir. Mar. 11, 1996) (comparing cases); see also Horner ex rel. Horner v. Ky. High Sch. Ath. Ass’n, 206 F.3d 685, 689–92, 690 n.2 (6th Cir. 2000) (citing Guardians Ass’n v. Civ. Serv. Comm’n of N.Y.C, 463 U.S. 582, 602 (1983)) (explaining that in Guardians, “a majority of the Court held that Title VI supports a private right of action providing limited declarative and injunctive relief for unintentional violations” while a different majority rejected monetary damages for unintentional discrimination). While Horner read Title IX in light of Guardians as permitting claims of unintentional discrimination, other courts have not reached the same conclusion. See Fort, 1996 U.S. App. LEXIS 44677, at *3 n.3 (comparing cases). Disparate impact discrimination occurs when a facially neutral policy or practice causes unequal outcomes for a protected class, but it does not require a showing of discriminatory intent.90See Univ. of Denver, 952 F.3d at 1193 n.8 (noting lack of requirement for intent). That said, courts required plaintiffs to prove intent to obtain money damages.91See, e.g., Horner, 206 F.3d at 689–92; Edgewood Indep., 964 F.3d at 358 (“Essentially, schools are liable only for intentional sex discrimination.”); cf. Parker v. Franklin Cnty. Cmty. Sch. Corp., 667 F.3d 910, 925 (7th Cir. 2012) (barring money damages against a party where plaintiffs failed to examine that party’s practices and any resulting harm). But in 2001, the Supreme Court held in Alexander v. Sandoval92532 U.S. 275 (2001). that Title VI prohibits only intentional discrimination and that a right of action therefore did not exist under Title VI for disparate impact discrimination.93Id. at 293. Although the Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit indicated that Title IX might provide non-monetary relief for unintentional discrimination,94See Parker, 667 F.3d at 925 (noting that schools that may have contributed to a scheduling disparity might be affected by an injunction but that plaintiffs could not recover monetary damages because the plaintiffs did not examine those schools’ overall practices or the resulting harm from those practices). since Sandoval, courts have generally viewed Title IX as prohibiting only intentional forms of discrimination.95See, e.g., Haidak v. Univ. of Mass.-Amherst, 933 F.3d 56, 75 (1st Cir. 2019) (“We have never recognized a private right of action for disparate-impact discrimination under Title IX.” (citing Sandoval, 532 U.S. at 283)); Biediger v. Quinnipiac Univ., 691 F.3d 85, 97–98 (2nd Cir. 2012) (recognizing that Title IX prohibits intentional discrimination, and that disputes about equal opportunities when sports are separated “on the basis of sex” involve “a disparate treatment rather than disparate impact claim”); Wolfe v. Fayetteville, Ark. Sch. Dist., 648 F.3d 860, 865 (8th Cir. 2011) (“[P]roof of sex-based motivation is required for a Title IX deliberate indifference claim.”); Weinreb v. Xerox Bus. Servs., No. 16-cv-6823, 2020 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 132134, at *9–10 (S.D.N.Y. July 27, 2020) (observing that the majority of “reasoned district court opinions interpreting Section 1557” do not affirm that Section 1557 creates a uniform standard, and holding that disparate impact claims are unavailable under Section 1557); Briscoe v. Health Care Serv. Corp., 281 F. Supp. 3d 725, 737–39 (N.D. Ill. 2017) (finding that grouping of sex and other protected classifications in Section 1557 of the Affordable Care Act did not create a private right of action for disparate impact claims for sex discrimination and rejecting Office of Civil Rights’ interpretation that the same standards applied to all protected classifications); Tsuruta v. Augustana Univ., No. 15-CV-04150, 2015 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 136796, at *8–9 (D.S.D. Oct. 7, 2015) (observing that although the Court of Appeals for the Tenth Circuit allowed disparate impact claims under Title IX based on a pre-Sandoval reading of Title VI, cases looking to Title VI to interpret Title IX after Sandoval concluded that Title IX does not allow disparate impact claims). But see Univ. of Denver, 952 F.3d at 1193 n.8 (observing that a different Court of Appeals for the Tenth Circuit case suggested availability of disparate impact claim but declining to resolve the question (citing Mabry v. State Bd. of Cmty. Colls. & Occupational Educ., 813 F.2d 311, 316 n.6, 318 (10th Cir. 1987))).

In Poloceno v. Dallas Independent School District,96826 F. App’x 359 (5th Cir. 2020) (unpublished). for example, a parent sued the school district after her daughter was hospitalized due to punishment for not wearing appropriate gym attire.97Id. at 361. The Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit held that the punishment—increasing numbers of “ceiling jumps” for repeat violations—was not intentional discrimination because it was equally applied to boys and girls.98Id. at 362. The court rejected the parent’s disparate impact claim, that girls were disproportionately affected, because “only intentional discrimination, not disparate impact, is actionable under Title IX.”99Id. at 362–63.

B.      Title VII’s Disparate Treatment Standard

The disparate treatment analysis under Title VII is markedly different than under Title IX. Under Title VII, to establish prima facie disparate treatment, an employee must generally show that the employee (1) “is a member of [a] protected class,” (2) “was qualified for [the] position,” (3) “experienced an adverse employment action,” and (4) was treated worse than “similarly situated individuals outside [the] protected class.”100Peterson v. Hewlett-Packard Co., 358 F.3d 599, 603 (9th Cir. 2004); see Mandell v. Cnty. of Suffolk, 316 F.3d 368, 377 (2d Cir. 2003) (listing the same factors); see also McDonnell Douglas Corp. v. Green, 411 U.S. 792, 802 (1973) (stating test as applied to race). A plaintiff can meet the fourth prong of the test by showing that “other circumstances surrounding the adverse employment action give rise to an inference of discrimination.”101Peterson, 358 F.3d at 603; see Mandell, 316 F.3d at 377; see also McDonnell Douglas, 411 U.S. at 802. The employer must then give a nondiscriminatory reason for the action, which the plaintiff can overcome “by a preponderance of the evidence” that the proffered basis was “a pretext.”102Young v. United Parcel Serv., Inc., 575 U.S. 206, 213 (2015) (quoting Tex. Dept. of Cmty. Affairs v. Burdine, 450 U.S. 248, 253 (1981)) (explaining burden shifting).

Because Title VII prohibits discrimination “because of” sex, sex stereotyping can evidence sex discrimination under Title VII.103See Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins, 490 U.S. 228, 250 (1989); see also Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1741 (2020) (relying on Price Waterhouse for proposition that Title VII prohibits any consideration of sex in employment decisions); id. at 1763–64 (Alito, J., dissenting) (observing that Price Waterhouse stands for the proposition that evidence of sex stereotyping “may be convincing where the trait that is inconsistent with the stereotype is one that would be tolerated and perhaps even valued in a person of the opposite sex”). In Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins,104490 U.S. 228 (1989). a plurality of the Supreme Court resolved a circuit split on the burdens of proof required for each party in a Title VII suit.105Id. at 232. In doing so, the plurality explained that sex stereotyping can be evidence of sex discrimination, even though engaging in stereotyping is not always itself Title VII sex discrimination.106Id. at 251. It reached this conclusion because an employer who acts based on a sex stereotype considers the person’s sex, which Title VII prohibits.107Id. at 241, 250. Even with evidence of sex stereotyping, however, a plaintiff still must prove that the employer would not have made the employment decision in question but for the employee’s sex.108Id. at 251. And an employer can show through a preponderance of the evidence that even if sex were a but-for cause, the employer is not liable because it would have arrived at the same decision without considering the employee’s sex.109Id. at 242, 253.

C.      Courts’ Interpretations of Title VII and Title IX

1.      Bostock and Title VII

In 2020, the Supreme Court held in Bostock v. Clayton County, Georgia that Title VII prohibits “fir[ing] an individual for being . . . transgender.”110Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1737 (2020). Such firing violates Title VII, the Court explained, because the employer “fire[d] that person for traits or actions it would not have questioned in members of a different sex.”111Id. Thus, sex impermissibly “play[ed] a necessary and undisguisable role in the decision.”112Id.

Bostock began by outlining a framework to determine whether a basis for an adverse employment action is intentional sex discrimination under Title VII.113Id. at 1739 (“The question isn’t just what ‘sex’ meant, but what Title VII says about it.”); id. at 1740 (“In so-called ‘disparate treatment’ cases like today’s, this Court has also held that the difference in treatment based on sex must be intentional. So, taken together, an employer who intentionally treats a person worse because of sex—such as by firing the person for actions or attributes it would tolerate in an individual of another sex—discriminates against that person in violation of Title VII.” (citations omitted)). Title VII prohibits “taking certain actions ‘because of’ sex.”114Id. In prior decisions, the Court, defined “because of” as “by reason of” or “on account of.”115Id. (quoting Univ. of Tex. Sw. Med. Ctr. v. Nassar, 570 U.S. 338, 350 (2013)). Put simply, Title VII bars an employer from making certain employment decisions because an employee has a particular sex.116Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1739. Thus, Title VII incorporates a “but-for causation” test, which examines whether “a particular outcome would not have happened ‘but for’ the purported cause.”117Id. (citing Gross v. FBL Fin. Servs., Inc., 557 U.S. 167, 176 (2009)). To determine whether “sex” was the “but-for” cause, the test “directs . . . chang[ing] one thing at a time and see[ing] if the outcome changes.”118Id. Even if multiple but-for causes are found, if the outcome changes when the only difference is sex, sex is one but-for cause in violation of Title VII.119Id.

The but-for test led the Court to conclude that firing an employee because of the employee’s transgender status constitutes sex discrimination.120Id. at 1737, 1741 (“[I]t is impossible to discriminate against a person for being . . . transgender without discriminating against that individual based on sex.”). The Court did not explicitly define “sex” in Title VII. Rather, it “proceed[ed] on the assumption that ‘sex’ . . . referr[ed] only to biological distinctions between male and female.”121Id. at 1739. The Court proceeded on such an assumption because the employees “concede[d] the point for argument’s sake” and “nothing in [the Court’s] approach . . . turn[ed] on the outcome of the parties’ debate.” Id. Applying the but-for test, the Court explained that when an employer discriminates against an employee for having transgender status, “two causal factors may be in play—both the individual’s sex and something else (the sex . . . with which the individual identifies).”122Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1742. To illustrate why, the Court gave the example of two employees, one “who was identified as male at birth but now identifies as a female” and “an otherwise identical employee who was identified as female at birth.”123Id. at 1741. If the employer fires the employee who was male at birth, the employer fired that employee “for traits or actions that it tolerates in an employee identified as female at birth.”124Id.

The Court viewed the discrimination in dispute as against an employee for having a transgender status.125Id. at 1737. Transgender status, as the Bostock Court understood it, arises from an incongruence between sex and gender identity.126As earlier noted, the Court proceeding on the assumption that “sex” in Title VII refers to a biological male-female binary. Id. at 1739. The Court, however, never uses the term “gender identity” except when referencing the employees’ understanding of “sex,” which it declined to adopt. See id. at 1739. Rather, it describes a transgender employee as having one sex at birth but now identifying with a different sex. Id. at 1742. Thus, transgender status is a signal that a person has a particular combination of sex and “something else”—a particular gender identity. The question, in the Court’s eyes, is thus whether the trait is problematic alone or whether the trait is only a problem because it occurs in combination with a particular sex.127See id. at 1744–45 (discussing objections to the Court’s conclusion). Comparing two employees with the same trait—identifying as a female—but with different sexes produces different outcomes.128Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1741. Thus, in the Court’s analysis, the adverse action turned on the employees’ sex.129Id. at 1741–42..

The Court did not reach this conclusion by finding that transgender status is “related to sex in some vague sense or because discrimination on [the basis of transgender status] has some disparate impact on one sex or another.”130Id. at 1742.. The Court reached this conclusion because discrimination “on [this] ground[ ] requires an employer to intentionally treat individual employees differently because of their sex.”131Id. Put another way, firing a person for having transgender status treats that person worse “for traits or actions [the employer] would not have questioned in members of a different sex.”132Id. at 1737. The tolerance of the traits thus depends on sex.133Id. at 1737, 1742.

The Court further presumed, however, that considering “sex” in the abstract is sufficient to trigger Title VII liability. As the dissent observed, merely stating that a person has transgender status says nothing about the person’s specific sex or specific gender identity.134See Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1758–59 (Alito, J., dissenting) (noting that an employer could refuse to hire a transgender person without knowing the person’s specific sex). The majority recognized as much, explaining that Title VII liability is triggered if an employer merely considers that the employee’s identity and sex do not align—even if the employee’s exact sex is otherwise unknown.135See id. at 1746 (majority opinion) (“[I]magine an applicant doesn’t know what the words homosexual or transgender mean. Then try writing out instructions for who should check the box without using the words man, woman, or sex . . . . It can’t be done. . . . Any way you slice it, the employer intentionally refuses to hire applicants in part because of the affected individuals’ sex, even if it never learns any applicant’s sex.”).

In sum, the Court reached its conclusion by assuming a binary, biologically rooted understanding of “sex” as used in the statute.136See A. Russell, Note, Bostock v. Clayton County: The Implications of a Binary Bias, 106 Cornell L. Rev. 1601, 1614 (2021) (citing Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1739). Bostock neither redefined “sex” to encompass gender identity137See Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1739; see also Russell, supra note 136, at 1614–15. nor held that discrimination because of gender identity is sex discrimination. On the contrary, it explicitly treated gender identity and sex as concepts that exist independent of each other.138See Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1742. Whether a person is transgender, in the Court’s eyes, turns on the relationship between sex and gender identity. If the two don’t align, the person has transgender status. If they do align, the person does not.

2.      Title IX in the Transgender Context

Although the Supreme Court declined to address Title IX in the transgender context,139See id. at 1753; West Virginia v. B.P.J., 143 S. Ct. 889, 889 (2023) (mem.) (Alito, J., dissenting from denial of application to vacate injunction). three federal courts of appeals have directly addressed whether Title IX permits treating a person consistent with that person’s biological sex when the person has transgender status.140See A.C. v. Metro. Sch. Dist. of Martinsville, 75 F.4th 760, 764 (7th Cir. 2023), petition for cert. filed, No. 23-392 (Oct. 11, 2023); Adams ex rel. Kasper v. Sch. Bd. of St. Johns Cnty., 57 F.4th 791, 796 (11th Cir. 2022); Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 972 F.3d 586, 593 (4th Cir. 2020); Whitaker v. Kenosha Unified Sch. Dist. No. 1 Bd. of Educ., 858 F.3d 1034, 1038–39 (7th Cir. 2017). Other federal courts of appeals have also addressed the question but did not do so substantively or on the merits. See supra note 23. The Courts of Appeals for the Fourth and Seventh Circuits, on different legal theories, concluded Title IX does not permit such treatment.141Compare Grimm, 972 F.3d at 618 (conducting disparate treatment analysis) with Whitaker, 858 F.3d at 1047–48 (applying sex stereotyping theory), and Martinsville, 75 F.4th at 771–72 (applying both Whitaker and Bostock). In contrast, the Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit, sitting en banc, held Title IX does allow such treatment.142Adams, 57 F.4th at 796 (holding that Title IX permits treating a person consistent with that person’s biological sex when the person has transgender status). Although the precise details vary, the overarching facts of the first three of these cases are similar.143Although the Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit addressed the issue twice, first in Whitaker and then in Martinsville, the latter followed Whitaker with no new analysis other than to also apply Bostock. See Martinsville, 75 F.4th at 769, 771–72. Because this examination of the circuit split seeks to illuminate the different lines of reasoning and Martinsville charted no new course, this section only examines Whitaker, Grimm, and Adams. That said, Part IV explains why the applications of Bostock in Grimm , the Adams dissent, and Martinsville were incorrect. Each plaintiff—Whitaker, Grimm, and Adams—was born female but identified as male.144Whitaker, 858 F.3d at 1040; Grimm, 972 F.3d at 597–98 (explaining that Grimm was “identified as female” at birth but “always knew he was a boy”); Adams, 57 F.4th at 796 (“Adams identifies as male, while Adams’s biological sex—sex based on chromosomal structure and anatomy at birth—is female.”). When the plaintiffs sought to use the male restrooms in their respective schools, however, they were ultimately denied access.145Whitaker, 858 F.3d at 1040, 1042; Grimm, 972 F.3d at 598–600 (explaining that Grimm was initially permitted to use the male bathroom but ultimately denied access under a new school board policy); Adams, 57 F.4th at 797–98. Each school instead offered the alternative of using a unisex restroom in addition to the female restroom.146Whitaker, 858 F.3d at 1040, 1042; Grimm, 972 F.3d at 599–600; Adams, 57 F.4th at 797–98.

a.      Whitaker v. Kenosha Unified School District

The Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit was the first of the three courts to decide whether Title IX compels a school to treat a student consistent with that student’s gender identity.147Whitaker, 858 F.3d at 1038–39. Applying Title VII sex-stereotyping precedents, the court explained that by barring Whitaker, a transgender male, from the male bathroom, Kenosha’s actions constituted a penalty for “gender non-conformance.”148Id. at 1049. The court therefore held that the school violated Title IX under a sex-stereotyping theory.149Id. at 1039.

The court began its Title IX analysis by explaining that a plaintiff can bring a claim under Title VII under a sex-stereotyping theory.150Id. at 1047 (citing Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins, 490 U.S. 228, 251 (1989)). The dispute, the court observed, was whether a “student who alleges discrimination on the basis of . . . transgender status can state a claim of sex discrimination” under Title IX.151Id. Title IX neither defined “sex” nor used the modifier “biological.”152Id. Although the court had previously read “sex” in Title VII narrowly to “exclude transsexuals,” the court explained that Price Waterhouse afterwards embraced “a broad view” that Title VII prohibits “disparate treatment . . . resulting from sex stereotypes.”153Whitaker, 858 F.3d at 1047–48 (first quoting Ulane v. E. Airlines, Inc., 742 F.2d 1081, 1085–86 (7th Cir. 1984) and then quoting Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins, 490 U.S. 228, 251 (1989)). And the Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit, as well as other courts, since then “have recognized a cause of action . . . when an adverse action is taken because of [a] . . . failure to conform to sex stereotypes.”154Id. at 1048.

Next, the court observed that transgender status arose from a person’s non-conformity with “sex-based stereotypes of the sex that he or she was assigned at birth.”155Id. Thus, as other courts have concluded, Title VII allows claims of discrimination based on transgender status.156Id. at 1048–49. The school district contended that “this reasoning flies in the face of Title IX” because Congress failed to make transgender status a protected classification under Title IX, but the court disagreed.157Id. at 1049. Congressional inaction, the court explained, could also indicate that the law already included the proposed change.158Id.

Whitaker was thus likely to prevail under Title IX because his complaint alleged that the district “denied him access . . . because he is transgender.”159Whitaker, 858 F.3d at 1049. In the court’s eyes, requiring a student “to use a bathroom that does not conform with his or her gender identity punishes that [student] for his or her gender non-conformance.”160Id. In other words, Kenosha subjected Whitaker “to different rules, sanctions, and treatment than non-transgender students.”161Id. And by making Whitaker the only student to use the single-user bathrooms, the district further extended this differential treatment.162Id. at 1050.

b.      Grimm v. Gloucester County School Board

The Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit reached the same conclusion in Grimm163Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 972 F.3d 586, 593 (4th Cir. 2020). as the court did in Whitaker164858 F.3d at 1039. but on a disparate treatment theory.165Grimm, 972 F.3d at 618 (comparing the school’s treatment of Grimm to its treatment of “other boys”). Relying on Bostock, the majority determined that the school board discriminated on the basis of sex.166Id. at 616–17. Bostock, the court observed, held that discrimination because of transgender status “is discrimination ‘on the basis of sex.’”167Id. at 616. That follows, the court explained, because the discriminator must “necessarily refer[ ] to the individual’s sex to determine incongruence between sex and gender.”168Id. (quoting Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1741–42 (2020)). Because the school board had to refer to Grimm’s sex to determine that Grimm could not use the male bathroom, Grimm’s sex was the “but-for cause” of the exclusion.169Id. Moreover, although Bostock did not address Title IX,170Id. (citing Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1753). discrimination under Title IX “mean[s] treating that individual worse than others who are similarly situated.”171Grimm, 972 F.3d at 618 (quoting Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1740). Grimm, the court stated, was treated worse than “other boys” because Grimm “could not use the restroom corresponding with his gender.”172Id.

Although Title IX permitted sex-separate bathrooms, the court further noted, the regulation cannot override the statute’s prohibition on sex discrimination.173Id. That said, Grimm challenged “discriminatory exclusion” from sex-separate restrooms, not those restrooms’ existence.174Id. And so the board could maintain sex-separate restrooms but could not “rely on its own discriminatory notions of what ‘sex’ means.”175Id. Put simply, the court explained, the board invented its own classification (“biological gender”), defined it as the sex marker on a birth certificate, and then refused to recognize an updated birth certificate.176Id. at 619. The court therefore affirmed the district court’s grant of summary judgment on Grimm’s Title IX claim.177Grimm, 972 F.3d at 619. The court also held that by refusing to update Grimm’s transcript, the school treated Grimm worse than other students because other students’ transcripts “reflect[ed] their correct sex” while Grimm’s did not. See id.

Judge Paul Niemeyer, dissenting, countered that Title IX in fact allowed separate restrooms on the basis of biological sex.178Id. at 637 (Niemeyer, J., dissenting). The term “sex” in Title IX, he argued, “must be understood as referring to the traditional biological indicators that distinguish a male from a female,” not a person’s gender identity or gender expression.179Id. at 632. First, he argued, dictionaries uniformly defined sex in that manner.180Id. at 632–33. Even Bostock, he noted, assumed that “sex” in Title VII—which was adopted about the same time as Title IX—referred to such biological distinctions.181Id. at 633 (citing Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1739 (2020)). Second, Title IX allows sex-separate facilities to protect individuals’ privacy interest in shielding their undressed bodies from members of the opposite sex.182Id. at 633–34. Indeed, the Supreme Court recognized that “‘physical differences between men and women’ are ‘enduring’ and render ‘the two sexes . . . not fungible.’”183Grimm, 972 F.3d at 634 (Niemeyer, J., dissenting) (quoting United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 533, 550 n.19 (1996)). Third, Grimm was born a biological female and thus was not similarly situated to students born biologically male.184Id. Because Title IX expressly authorized separate bathrooms based on sex, Judge Niemeyer concluded, the majority’s opinion was a statement on how transgender students should be treated, not what Title IX requires.185Id. at 635.

c.      Adams v. School Board of St. Johns County

Echoing Judge Niemeyer’s argument in Grimm, the Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit held in December 2022 that the “unremarkable—and nearly universal—practice of separating school bathrooms based on biological sex” did not violate Title IX.186Adams ex rel. Kasper v. Sch. Bd. of St. Johns Cnty., 57 F.4th 791, 796 (11th Cir. 2022). The panel also resolved Adams’ equal protection claim in favor of the school. Id.. Beginning with the text of Title IX and its implementing regulations, the court explained that the appeal required interpretation of the term “sex.”187Id. at 811–12. Because Title IX included statutory and regulatory “carve-outs for differentiating between the sexes,” the court could not simply determine whether discrimination on the basis of transgender status is sex discrimination.188Id. at 811. After all, the court noted, if “sex” refers to “biological sex,” then the carve-out for separate bathrooms “on the basis of sex” permits the Board’s policy.189Id.

Title IX is not ambiguous, the court concluded.190Id. at 812–13. As “[r]eputable dictionary definitions” demonstrate, including the dictionary relied on by the district court, “sex” when Title IX was adopted referred to “biological sex.”191Id. at 812. And because ambiguity arises from a statute’s context rather than possible definitions, Title IX’s lack of a definition of “sex” does not evidence ambiguity.192Adams, 57 F.4th at 813 (quoting Brown v. Gardner, 513 U.S. 115, 118 (1994)). On the contrary, the court explained, Title IX’s carve-outs reveal that sex must refer to biology.193Id. Title IX, for instance, permits sex-separate living facilities.194Id. If sex were ambiguous or included gender identity, the court reasoned, then a transgender student could live in housing corresponding with the student’s sex and housing corresponding with the student’s gender identity.195Id. The carve-out for sex-separate housing would make no sense.196Id.

The court then rejected the argument that prior cases had read “gender identity” or “transgender status” into the meaning of “sex.”197Id. Bostock, the court explained, proceeded on the assumption that “sex” in Title VII referred to “biological distinctions” and did not define sex to include transgender status.198Adams, 57 F.4th at 813–14 (quoting Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1739 (2020)). Price Waterhouse and the Court of Appeals for the Eleventh Circuit’s own precedent only dealt with sex stereotypes in the workplace and did not “depart[ ] from the plain meaning of ‘sex.’”199Id. (citing Price Waterhouse v. Hopkins, 490 U.S. 228, 250 (1989); Glenn v. Brumby, 663 F.3d 1312, 1318–19 (11th Cir. 2011)). And “‘sex’ is not a stereotype,” the court added.200Id. Contrary to the district court’s assumption, “sex” does not mean one thing for a transgender person and another for a non-transgender person.201Id. at 813–14. Because Title IX expressly allows bathrooms separated on the basis of sex, the majority further observed, a non-transgender biological female would fail legally in a demand to use the male restroom.202Id. at 814. Adams’ claim, therefore, failed as well.203Id. at 814–15.

The court further noted that the district court’s interpretation would create a “dual protection” that elevates protections for transgender status over protections for sex.204Adams, 57 F.4th at 814. Under the district court’s reading, “an entity would be prohibited from installing or enforcing the otherwise permissible sex-based carve-outs when the carve-outs come into conflict with a transgender person’s gender identity.”205Id. This, the majority charged, does not align with Title IX’s purpose or the plain meaning of “sex” when Title IX was adopted.206Id.

Even if Title IX was ambiguous, the majority concluded, the Spending Clause compelled ruling in the school’s favor on Adams’s Title IX claim.207Id. at 815. Congress is expected to speak clearly when it places a condition on federal funds.208Id. at 815–16. The widespread practice of separating bathrooms and living facilities based on biological sex, the majority argued, belies the notion that the School Board should have been on notice that its policy violated Title IX.209Id. at 816. Moreover, Adams’s interpretation would impact not only bathrooms but also living facilities, locker rooms, and sports.210See Adams, 57 F.4th at 816. “Absent a clear statement from Congress,” the majority concluded, “such a reading . . . would offend first principles of statutory interpretation and judicial restraint.”211Id. at 817.

The opinion was accompanied by a brief concurrence and four dissents. Judge Barbara Lagoa, concurring, argued that redefining sex would adversely impact women’s sports.212Id. at 817–21 (Lagoa, J., concurring). Judge Charles Wilson, dissenting, charged that sex is “not static” based on intersex conditions.213Id. at 821–23 (Wilson, J., dissenting). Because intersex students might change their respective sexes or have genitalia that do not align with their sex, Judge Wilson argued, the Board’s policy discriminates on the basis of biological sex and does not solve privacy concerns.214Id. at 822–24. Judges Adalberto Jordan and Robin Rosenbaum, also dissenting, only focused on Adams’s equal protection claim.215Id. at 824 (Jordan, J., dissenting); id. at 830 (Rosenbaum, J., dissenting).. Judge Jill Pryor, however, offered a substantive critique of the majority’s Title IX analysis.216Adams, 57 F.4th at 832–33, 856–59 (Pryor, J., dissenting). Judge Pryor also offered an equal protection analysis, but that is beyond the scope of this Comment. See id. at 832, 844–55.

First, Judge Pryor argued, the majority reframed the case.217Id. at 842. The school board, she stated, defined “biological sex” as “anatomical” or “physiological” sex but declined to define either term.218Id. at 836–37, 836 n.3. The board’s definition of biological sex, she wrote, was “the sex a doctor assigns an infant in the moments after birth by examining the infant’s external genitalia.”219Id. at 836. This definition, she proceeded to argue, broke with the scientific communities’ understanding of sex, which she asserted encompassed physical traits as well as gender identity.220Id. at 836–37. And it ignored that biological components might diverge and that gender identity is the primary determinant of sex.221Id. at 836–37, 836 n.4. By defining “biological sex” as “sex based on chromosomal structure and anatomy at birth,” Judge Pryor charged, the majority ignored the record, including the School Board’s definition of sex.222Adams, 57 F.4th at 842. Moreover, the case was about discrimination against transgender students, she contested, not “the legality of sex-separated bathrooms.”223Id. at 843.

Judge Pryor proceeded to determine that the exclusion was discriminatory.224Id. at 856. Cisgender students, she explained, could use the restroom corresponding with their gender identities, but transgender students could not.225Id. Assuming that sex in Title IX refers unambiguously to biological sex, she then explained that sex includes gender identity.226Id. at 856–57. Thus, a person “can be male if some biological components of sex, including gender identity, align with maleness.”227Id. at 857.

Next, Judge Pryor argued that “on the basis of” imposed the but-for causation test.228Adams, 57 F.4th at 857. Applying Bostock, she explained that “Adams was excluded from the boys’ bathroom under the policy . . . because he had one specific biological marker traditionally associated with females, genital anatomy (or, put differently, because he lacked that one specific biological marker traditionally associated with males).”229Id. at 857–58. Thus, Judge Pryor concluded, Adams was excluded on the basis of sex.230Id. at 858.

Judge Pryor further argued that the carve-outs did not rescue the policy.231Id. at 859. The carveouts do not address, she stated, what facility a person should use when the person’s “biological markers of . . . sex point in different directions.”232Id. Adams, she observed, has both male and female biological markers as a transgender boy.233Id. Thus, Adams’s claim “is not foreclosed by the Title IX carveouts.”234Adams, 57 F.4th at 859.

Judge Pryor concluded by asserting that allowing transgender students to use the bathroom corresponding with their respective gender identities would not turn private facilities or sports teams “into sex-neutral areas and activities.”235Id. (quoting id. at 817 (majority opinion)). Adams’ case, she explained, did not address “how to assign gender fluid individuals”—individuals “whose gender changes between male and female.”236Id. Moreover, she argued, that “sex is a but-for cause of differential treatment does not necessarily mean that actionable discrimination exists.”237Id. at 860. But “[w]here exclusion implies inferiority, as it does here, principles of equality prevail.”238Id.. By excluding Adams from the boys’ bathroom, she emphasized, the school placed on Adams “a ‘badge of inferiority.’”239Id. (quoting Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 976 F.3d 399, 403 (4th Cir. 2020) (Wynn, J., concurring in denial of reh’g en banc).

III.      The Original Understanding of Title IX

Title IX permits treating a person as male or female based on that person’s sex, even if that person has transgender status. As originally understood, “sex” in Title IX refers to whether a person is male or female based on how the person’s body is reproductively organized. And as the text, contemporary understandings, and subsequent early interpretations of Title IX by the executive branch and Congress demonstrate, Title IX’s requirement is one of equal opportunity, not sex blindness. Title IX’s disparate treatment test thus looks at whether students are given equal opportunities and access to benefits or are subject to the same standards—not whether sex was ever considered.

A.      The Meaning of “Sex”

1.      Historical Understandings of “Sex”

The Adams majority rightly understood Adams’s sex as female because the sex of a claimant in the Title IX context must be understood as it would have been when Title IX was adopted. After all, Title IX prohibits discrimination “on the basis of sex.” What that means, however, depends on what “sex” is.240See id. at 811. And as the majority and Judge Pryor’s disagreement in Adams illustrates, in the transgender context, the definition of “sex” matters.241See also A.C. v. Metro. Sch. Dist. of Martinsville, 75 F.4th 760, 775 (7th Cir. 2023) (Easterbrook, J., concurring in the judgment) (observing that if Title IX uses “sex” in “a genetic sense,” as he believes it does “given that word’s normal usage when the statute was enacted,” Title IX “does not compel states” to treat as a male an individual who presents as male but has a female sex), petition for cert. filed, No. 23-392 (Oct. 11, 2023).

But “sex” is not whatever anyone says it is. Once a term is embedded in a statute, its definition is static rather than evolving over time.242See Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1738 (2020) (“This Court normally interprets a statute in accord with the ordinary public meaning of its terms at the time of its enactment. After all, only the words on the page constitute the law adopted by Congress and approved by the President.”); id. at 1766 (Alito, J., dissenting) (“The words of a law . . . ‘mean what they conveyed to reasonable people at the time.’” (quoting Antonin Scalia & Bryan A. Garner, Reading Law: The Interpretation of Legal Texts 16 (2012))); id. at 1825 (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting) (“[C]ourts must adhere to the ordinary meaning of phrases, not just the meaning of the words in a phrase. . . . The ordinary meaning that counts is the ordinary public meaning at the time of enactment . . . .”); Wisc. Cent. Ltd. v. United States, 138 S. Ct. 2067, 2070 (2018) (“[O]ur job is to interpret the words consistent with their ‘ordinary meaning . . . at the time Congress enacted the statute.’” (quoting Perrin v. United States, 444 U.S. 37, 42 (1979))). Terms and phrases bear the ordinary public meaning they bore when Congress placed them into the statute.243See Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1738 (looking to the “ordinary public meaning of [the statute’s] terms at the time of its enactment”); id. at 1766 (Alito, J., dissenting) (likewise examining the terms’ original meaning); id. at 1825 (Kavanaugh, J., dissenting) (looking at “the ordinary public meaning at the time of enactment”); Wisc. Cent., 138 S. Ct. at 2070. What a statute means is the same as what it meant when enacted, regardless of what the same words or terms mean today.244See Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1750 (“Because the law’s ordinary meaning at the time of enactment usually governs, we must be sensitive to the possibility a statutory term that means one thing today or in one context might have meant something else at the time of its adoption . . . .”). By prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sex, Title IX prohibits discrimination on the basis of sex as sex was understood when Title IX was adopted.

“Sex” at the time of Title IX’s enactment—and for years afterwards—referred to a male-female binary determined by the wholistic organization of a person’s body for reproductive function.245See, e.g., Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1784–91 (Alito, J., dissenting) (listing various dictionary definitions of “sex” published between 1953 and 2011); Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 972 F.3d 586, 632–33 (4th Cir. 2020) (Niemeyer, J., dissenting) (listing definitions from dictionaries published between 1970 and 1980); Adams, 57 F.4th at 812 (listing definitions from dictionaries published between 1970 to 1980); Sex, Black’s Law Dictionary (6th ed. 1990) (“The sum of the peculiarities of structure and function that distinguish a male from a female organism; the character of being male or female.”); Sex, The Oxford English Dictionary (2d ed. 1991) (defining “sex” as “[e]ither of the two divisions of organic beings distinguished as male and female respectively,” or “[t]he sum of those differences in the structure and function of the reproductive organs on the ground of which beings are distinguished as male and female, and of the other physiological differences consequent on these; the class of phenomena with which these differences are concerned”). See also Gender, Bryan A. Garner, A Dictionary of Modern Legal Usage (2d ed. 1995) (“[G]ender has long been used as a grammatical distinction of a word according to the sex referred to. It has newly been established in the language of the law in phrases such as gender-based discrimination, a use disapproved as jargonistic by some authorities. What this adds to sex discrimination, aside from eight letters and one hyphen, one can only guess.”); Gender, Webster’s Dictionary of English Usage (1989) (explaining the use of “gender” to refer to “sex”). Societal views at the time of Title IX’s enactment also reflected this understanding.246See supra Part I; see also 1970 Hearings, Part 1, supra note 46, at 437 (statement of Daisy Shaw, Director of Educational and Vocational Guidance of New York City) (noting that the concentration of women in certain professions seems “cultural” rather than “biological” because it “is based on cultural factors and societal expectations rather than on sex-linked characteristics or aptitudes.” (emphasis added)). By arguing that a woman’s social roles should not be defined by her body, for instance, the feminists of the mid-twentieth century reaffirmed that a woman is a woman because of how her body is reproductively organized. Witnesses in the 1970 hearings repeatedly recognized the existence of bona fide sex distinctions. And the policy debates following Title IX’s adoption reflected the view that the fundamental difference between males and females is physical.247See supra Part I. Title IX’s adoption sent a clear message: one’s body should not determine one’s opportunities. Unlike in the Title VII context, where the Court recognized debate over whether “sex” includes societal norms,248See Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1739. in the Title IX context, “sex” unequivocally does not refer to such norms.

Moreover, as the Adams majority observed, the context of Title IX further demonstrates that the ordinary meaning of sex referred to a male-female binary, not gender identity.249See Adams, 57 F.4th at 813 (critiquing impact of redefinition of sex on housing); J. Brad Reich, A (Not So) Simple Question: Does Title IX Encompass “Gender”?, 51 J. Marshall L. Rev. 225, 230–32 (2018) (observing that “Title IX . . . reflected a then binary sex worldview” and “recognized just two sexes (male and female)”). Today, far more than two gender identities are recognized.250Reich, supra note 249, at 231 (explaining that “the number of potential genders is infinite”); Kendall Tietz, Over 100 Gender, Sexuality Options on Application for San Francisco’s Guaranteed Transgender Income Program, Fox News (Nov. 19, 2022, 1:01 PM), https://perma.cc/TS4A-XRWH; Perri O. Blumberg, Emily Becker & Sabrina Talbert, Here’s Your Comprehensive Gender Identity List, as Defined by Psychologists and Sex Experts, WomensHealth (July 21, 2022), https://perma.cc/84YB-4FQC (listing several gender identities); Carlo Moleiro & Nuno Pinto, Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity: Review of Concepts, Controversies and Their Relation to Psychopathology Classification Systems, 6 Frontiers in Psych., Oct. 2015, at 1, 2, https://perma.cc/9CSN-WLKG (“The concept of gender identity evolved over time to include those people who do not identify either as female or male . . . .”). But Title IX speaks in terms of a binary.251Reich, supra note 249, at 232. For instance, the 1979 HEW Interpretation repeatedly referred to “the other sex” and “male and female” in outlining standards for treating both sexes equally.252See Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972; a Policy Interpretation; Title IX and Intercollegiate Athletics, 44 Fed. Reg. 71399, 71416–18 (Dec. 11, 1979); see also Nondiscrimination on the Basis of Sex in Education Programs or Activities Receiving Federal Financial Assistance, 34 C.F.R. § 106.41 (2023). Courts have given the 1975 HEW Regulations and 1979 HEW Interpretation “particularly high” deference. See Biediger v. Quinnipiac Univ., 691 F.3d 85, 97 (2d Cir. 2012) (quoting McCormick ex rel. McCormick v. Sch. Dist. of Mamaroneck, 370 F.3d 275, 288 (2d Cir. 2004)); Cohen v. Brown Univ., 991 F.2d 888, 895 (1st Cir. 1993) (giving the Department of Education’s replication of HEW’s regulations after HEW was divided into two agencies “particularly high” deference “because Congress explicitly delegated to the agency the task of prescribing standards for athletic programs under Title IX”); see also supra note 71 and accompanying text (explaining that some commenters to the notice of proposed rulemaking argued that by reviewing and accepting the 1975 rule and HEW’s 1979 interpretation, and then adopting the executive branch’s understanding of Title IX in the 1988 Civil Rights Restoration Act, Congress ratified HEW’s 1975 and 1979 understanding of Title IX). Even today, the Department of Education’s regulations require that “toilet, locker room, and shower facilities” that are provided “on the basis of sex . . . for students of one sex” are “comparable to such facilities provided for students of the other sex.”25334 C.F.R. § 106.33.

Bostock does not compel a contrary understanding of sex in Title IX. Even if its reasoning did apply in the Title IX context, it would not require finding that the term “sex” encompasses gender identity or transgender status. Bostock stated that “transgender status [is] inextricably bound up with sex,” but not because transgender status and sex are related.254Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1742 (2020). The Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit in Grimm explained why:

As the Supreme Court noted, “it is impossible to discriminate against a person for being homosexual or transgender without discriminating against that individual based on sex.” That is because the discriminator is necessarily referring to the individual’s sex to determine incongruence between sex and gender, making sex a but-for cause for the discriminator’s actions.255Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 972 F.3d 586, 616 (4th Cir. 2020) (citing Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1741–45).

The court in Grimm correctly understood what Bostock said about the relationship between sex, gender identity, and transgender status. Under Bostock, transgender status arises from an incongruence between a person’s sex and gender identity.256Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1742 (“When an employer fires an employee because she is . . . transgender, two causal factors may be in play—both the individual’s sex and something else (the sex . . . with which the individual identifies).”). Moreover, Bostock treats gender identity as an independent trait distinct from sex.257Id. at 1737, 1742 (describing discrimination because of transgender status as discrimination for having a sex in combination with another trait); id. at 1739, 1741 (applying the but-for test, which tests for discrimination by changing “one thing at a time,” and comparing two individuals with the same gender identity but different sexes). After all, the Court in Bostock “proceed[ed] on the assumption that ‘sex’ signified . . . only to biological distinctions between male and female.”258Id. at 1739. Bostock did not weave gender identity or transgender status into any definition of sex or make gender identity and sex even somewhat conceptually related.259But see, e.g., Amy Post, Ashley Stephens & Valarie Blake, Sex Discrimination in Healthcare: Section 1557 and LGBTQ Rights After Bostock, 11 Cal. L. Rev. Online 545, 546 (2021) (arguing that “sex discrimination under Section 1557 necessarily encompasses gender identity . . . discrimination after Bostock”); Abbey Widick, It is Time to Move Forward…On the Basis of Sex: The Impact of Bostock v. Clayton County on the Interpretation of “Sex” Under Title IX, 68 Wash. U.J.L. & Pol’y 303, 304 (2022) (arguing for the application of Bostock’s but-for test to prohibit gender identity discrimination under Title IX). This reasoning is incorrect, however, for the reasons stated by the Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit in Grimm and as explained above in Section II.C.2.b.

In sum, contrary to the definition proposed by the Adams dissent, “sex” was not defined by gender identity at the time of Title IX’s adoption. Nor was it understood as determined by gender identity in the years following when Title IX’s implementing regulations were promulgated.260See supra note 245 and accompanying text. Rather, “sex” was defined solely by the wholistic organization of the body for reproductive function.261See supra note 245 and accompanying text. This definition of sex has endured and continues to be used today.262See Bostock, 140 S. Ct. at 1784–91 (Alito, J., dissenting) (listing dictionary definitions of “sex” from many different years, including 2001 and 2011); Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 972 F.3d 586, 632–33 (4th Cir. 2020) (Niemeyer, J., dissenting) (listing definitions from 2011 and 2014 and explaining that “even today, the word ‘sex’ continues to be defined based on the physiological distinctions between males and females”); Sex, Britannica.com, https://perma.cc/3NAG-34UZ (explaining that “sex” is “the sum of features by which members of species can be divided into two groups—male and female—that complement each other reproductively” and that “[d]ifferentiation between the sexes exists, therefore, as the primary difference represented by the distinction between eggs and sperm, by differences represented by nature of the reproductive glands and their associated structures, and lastly by differences, if any, between individuals possessing the male and female reproductive tissues, respectively”); Sex, Black’s Law Dictionary (11th ed. 2019) (“The sum of the peculiarities of structure and function that distinguish a male from a female organism; gender.”); see also Anderson, supra note 12, at 78 & nn.1–3 (discussing three prominent embryology texts’ definition of sex as defined by chromosomes at the moment of fertilization); Brian Moulton & Liz Seaton, Hum. Rts. Campaign Found.,Transgender Americans: A Handbook for Understanding 5 (2005), https://www.bsu.edu/-/media/www/departmentalcontent/counselingcenter/pdfs/safezone-transgender/transgendered-issues-handbook.pdf (contrasting gender identity with “physical sex”). But see Anderson, supra note 12, at 28–33 (discussing newer definitions of sex that distinguish, for instance, between biological sex and sex assigned at birth). Because of that historical understanding of “sex,” the Courts of Appeals for the Fourth and Seventh Circuits erred when they treated students having the female sex but who identified as male as boys.263See Grimm, 972 F.3d at 618; Whitaker v. Kenosha Unified Sch. Dist. No. 1 Bd. of Educ., 858 F.3d 1034, 1049 (7th Cir. 2017); A.C. v. Metro. Sch. Dist. of Martinsville, 75 F.4th 760, 764 (describing the plaintiffs, biological females who identify as male, as “three boys [who] are transgender”), petition for cert. filed, No. 23-392 (Oct. 11, 2023).. Those cases were not about two classes of boys, one transgender and one not. Regardless of how the students identified, through the lens of Title IX, those cases were about girls who wanted to be treated identically to boys. That should have been the courts’ starting point, as it was in Adams. No matter a person’s gender identity, in a Title IX disparate treatment analysis, that person must be viewed as male or female based solely on that person’s sex.

2.      Intersex Conditions

Moreover, contrary to the Adams dissent’s claims, intersex conditions do not demonstrate that a person’s sex can change and thus do not prove that a person with transgender status could in fact become a different sex for the purposes of Title IX. Judge Wilson’s dissent in Adams makes much of intersex conditions to argue that sex is fungible, but his argument misses the point of the evidence he relies on. As he recognizes, intersex conditions are “conditions of physiological development.”264Adams ex rel. Kasper v. Sch. Bd. of St. Johns Cnty., 57 F.4th 791, 822 (11th Cir. 2022) (Wilson, J., dissenting); see also Ambiguous Genitalia, Mayo Clinic, https://perma.cc/D6DF-ZCT2 (“Ambiguous genitalia isn’t a disease; it’s a disorder of sex development.”); see also Anderson, supra note 12 at 88–91 (observing that intersex status is not a third sex but a disorder of development).. In other words, the body deviated from a biological norm in development.265See Ambiguous Genitalia, supra note 264. When a person has 5-alpha reductase, for instance, the person might physically appear as female until puberty or later, when testosterone triggers the development of male genitalia.266Adams, 57 F.4th at 822–23 (Wilson, J., dissenting). In that circumstance, the dissent explains, the discovery of underlying male physiological traits “would most certainly” cause medical professionals to “recategorize” the individual as male.267Id. at 823. Contrary to the dissent’s inference, the changing of a sex marker as more becomes known about a person’s body does not demonstrate that the person’s sex changes. It only demonstrates that the recognition of sex changes. The underlying attributes that define what sex is recognized remain constant.

Put simply, having an intersex condition is very different from having transgender status.268See id. at 822 (observing that having an intersex condition is not the same as having a transgender identity). Attempts to change the sex marker or physical attributes of an individual with an intersex condition are attempts to bring the body and recognition of sex into wholistic alignment with the underlying physical determinant of reproductive function.269See id. at 822–23 (observing that when a person’s physical attributes and chromosomes differ, once the disparity becomes apparent, the medical community “would most certainly” change its recognition of the person’s sex to reflect chromosomes rather than the maldeveloped genitalia). And while such a change reduces disharmony with gamete production and other biological traits determinative of reproductive function, aligning a person’s body with a gender identity increases disharmony.270See Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 972 F.3d 586, 596 (4th Cir. 2020) (observing that person with gender dysphoria may change their sex characteristics via hormonal treatment and surgery). The implication is that under Title IX’s understanding of sex, changes to the body or sex marker of an intersex person means something very different than the same changes for a transgender individual. Perhaps, under the Adams dissent’s understanding of sex,271Adams, 57 F.4th at 836–37 (Pryor, J., dissenting). Note that the dissent’s understanding of sex appears to be a minority view among the scientific and medical community. See, e.g., Sex and Sexuality, Am. Psych. Ass’n, https://perma.cc/6465-UGG4 (“Sex usually refers to the biological aspects of maleness or femaleness, whereas gender implies the psychological, behavioral, social, and cultural aspects of being male or female (i.e., masculinity or femininity). . . . Sexuality encompasses all aspects of sexual behavior, including gender identity, orientation, attitudes, and activity.”); Sex, Britannica.com, https://perma.cc/3NAG-34UZ (explaining that “sex” is “the sum of features by which members of species can be divided into two groups—male and female—that complement each other reproductively” and that “[d]ifferentiation between the sexes exists, therefore, as the primary difference represented by the distinction between eggs and sperm, by differences represented by nature of the reproductive glands and their associated structures, and lastly by differences, if any, between individuals possessing the male and female reproductive tissues, respectively”); Sex, Gender, and Sexuality, Nat’l Insts. of Health, https://perma.cc/V26T-4BVX (defining “sex” as “[a] biological category based on reproductive, anatomical, and genetic characteristics” but “gender identity” as a “sense of being a man, woman, boy, girl, genderqueer, nonbinary, etc. . . . [that] is not necessarily visible to others”); Sex and Gender: What’s the Difference, PsychCentral, https://perma.cc/X3MR-Z9QG (observing that sex and gender identity may not align, not that sex is determined by gender identity). such changes might mean the same thing for both, but that is not the definition of sex that Title IX employs. Sex is simply “not fungible.”272United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S 515, 533 (1996) (quoting Ballard v. United States, 329 U.S 187, 193 (1946) (“Physical differences between men and women, however, are enduring: ‘[T]he two sexes are not fungible . . . .’”)). Under Title IX, a biological male who identifies as a female and undergoes surgical and hormonal treatments to appear as female does not become a biological female.

B.      What Title IX Says About “Sex”

All that said, “[t]he question isn’t just what ‘sex’ meant, but what Title [IX] says about it.”273See Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1739 (2020) (discussing Title VII). As explained above, courts have traditionally interpreted Title IX as employing a disparate treatment test focused on equal opportunity.274See supra note 7 and accompanying text; see also supra Section II.A. And that is correct. The text and original understandings of Title IX demonstrate that Title IX mandates equal opportunity, not sex-blind treatment.

Turning to the text, Title IX states, “No person . . . shall, on the basis of sex, be excluded from participation in, be denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under” a federally funded education program or activity.27520 U.S.C. § 1681(a). This language resembles Title VI’s, which simply states, “No person in the United States shall, on the ground of race, color, or national origin, be excluded from participation in, be denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under any program or activity receiving Federal financial assistance.”27642 U.S.C. § 2000d. The resemblance is unsurprising considering that Title IX was modeled on Title VI.277See supra Part I (describing the development of Title IX). But unlike Title VI, which applies to “any” federally funded program or activity, Title IX applies only to federally funded education programs or activities.278Compare 42 U.S.C. § 2000d (banning discrimination under “any program” (emphasis added)), with 20 U.S.C. § 1681(a) (banning discrimination under “any education program” (emphasis added)). And while Title VI contains no exceptions, Title IX is riddled with them.279Compare 42 U.S.C. § 2000d (listing zero exceptions), with 20 U.S.C. § 1681(a) (listing nine exceptions).

Moreover, unlike Title VI, which bans any consideration of race,280See Students for Fair Admissions, Inc. v. President & Fellows of Harvard Coll., 143 S. Ct. 2141, 2209 (2023) (Gorsuch, J., concurring) (“[A] recipient of federal funds may never discriminate based on race, color, or national origin—period.”). Title IX does not mandate sex blindness. Within the context of education programs and activities, Title IX prohibits exclusion, the denial of benefits, and discrimination on the basis of sex. “Discrimination” at the time of Title IX’s adoption referred to “improper distinctions,”281Discrimination, Radin Law Dictionary (Lawrence G. Greene ed., 2d ed. 1970). such as not treating people “alike according to the standards and rule of action prescribed.”282Discrimination, Ballantine’s Law Dictionary (2d ed. 1969); see also Students for Fair Admissions, 143 S. Ct. at 2208–09 (2023) (Gorsuch, J., concurring) (defining “discrimination” as “to make a difference in treatment or favor on a class or categorical basis” (quoting Discrimination, Webster’s Third New International Dictionary (1961))). Put another way, it referred to treating a person “worse than others . . . similarly situated.”283See Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1740 (2020) (defining “discrimination” in Title VII as it was understood in 1964); see also CSX Transp., Inc. v. Ala. Dept. of Revenue, 562 U.S. 277, 286 (2011) (defining “discrimination” as a “failure to treat all persons equally when no reasonable distinction can be found between those favored and those not favored” (quoting Discrimination, Black’s Law Dictionary (5th ed. 1979))). But as contemporaneously understood, “inherent differences” exist between the sexes; “[p]hysical differences between men and women . . . are enduring.”284United States v. Virginia, 518 U.S. 515, 533 (1996); see supra Part I & Section III.A.1 (describing contemporaneous understandings of “sex”). Consequently, as witnesses from the Department of Justice and the Civil Rights Commission in the 1970 hearings, members of Congress at the time of Title IX’s adoption, and HEW shortly thereafter all recognized, men and women are not similarly situated in all circumstances.285See supra Part I and notes 50–52, 62 (discussing concerns about bona fide distinctions between men and women and the need to account for differences between the two); Nondiscrimination on the Basis of Sex in Education Programs and Activities Receiving or Benefiting from Federal Financial Assistance, 40 Fed. Reg. 24128, 24132 (June 4, 1975). In its 2020 Title IX regulations, the Department of Education reaffirmed this view:

In promulgating regulations to implement Title IX, the Department expressly acknowledged physiological differences between the male and female sexes. For example, the Department’s justification for not allowing schools to use “a single standard of measuring skill or progress in physical education classes . . . [if doing so] has an adverse effect on members of one sex”  was that “if progress is measured by determining whether an individual can perform twenty-five push-ups, the standard may be virtually out-of-reach for many more women than men because of the difference in strength between average persons of each sex.”

Nondiscrimination on the Basis of Sex in Education Programs or Activities Receiving Federal Financial Assistance, 85 Fed. Reg. 30026, 30178 (May 19, 2020) (quoting Nondiscrimination on the Basis of Sex in Education Programs and Activities Receiving or Benefiting from Federal Financial Assistance , 40 Fed. Reg. at 24132). In those circumstances, Title IX’s plain language permits differentiating between the sexes so long as neither is denied equal access to an education program, activity, or benefit.

This perhaps explains why Title IX lacked an exemption for bona fide distinctions between the sexes.286Compare 1970 Hearings, Part 2, supra note 49, at 678 (describing proposals that included an exemption), with 20 U.S.C. § 1681 (omitting any general exemption for bona fide distinctions). An explicit exemption was unnecessary. And it also explains why, despite Title IX’s lack of an express exemption for athletics, Congress permitted the 1975 HEW regulations to take effect—and then in 1988 expressly reaffirmed without qualification that the executive branch’s understanding of Title IX was correct.287See, e.g., Jocelyn Samuels & Kristen Galles, In Defense of Title IX: Why Current Policies Are Required to Ensure Equality of Opportunity, 14 Marq. Sports L. Rev. 11, 23–24 (2003) (“Congress thus confirmed the strong message it had sent when the regulations were first promulgated—that those regulations and, by 1987, the 1979 Policy Interpretation explaining them—correctly reflected Congress’ intent with regard to Title IX’s application to athletics.”); Alliance Defending Freedom, Comment Letter, supra note 71, at 4–5; Sarah Parshall Perry, Comment Letter, supra note 71, at 9–10. As Congress’s approval of both those rules and the later 1979 interpretation illustrates, under Title IX, the physical differences between the sexes may be considered as long as each sex is not denied equal educational opportunities.288See Samuels & Galles, supra note 287, at 22–24. In sum, Title IX requires equal treatment, not identical treatment.

Of course, this all begs the question of what an “improper” distinction or “worse” treatment—discrimination—is in the context of education programs and activities. After all, Title IX doesn’t simply bar federal-funding recipients who maintain such programs from ever engaging in sex discrimination; on the contrary, it bars subjecting someone to such discrimination “under” those programs. Under the canon of noscitur a sociis—”it is known by its associates”—when terms are used “in a context suggesting that the words have something in common, they should be assigned a permissible meaning that makes them similar.”289Scalia & Garner, supra note 242, at 195. Title IX’s requirements collectively focus on access to education programs, activities, and benefits.290See 20 U.S.C. § 1681. Immediately before prohibiting subjecting a person to discrimination, Title IX prohibits both exclusion from and denial of benefits.291Id. And Title IX prohibits specifically subjecting a person to discrimination “under” a federally funded education program or activity.292Id. In sum, looking to the associates of “discrimination,” “discrimination” cannot refer to mere differential treatment. Instead, it refers to disparate treatment that denies a person equal educational opportunities because that person is either male or female.

IV.      (Mis)Applying Bostock to Title IX

Despite Title IX’s unique structure and operation, courts disagree on whether Title VII’s principles regarding sex discrimination in the employment context apply under Title IX. Some courts of appeals look to Title VII as an informative analogue for defining Title IX standards.293See, e.g., Doe v. Snyder, 28 F.4th 103, 114 (9th Cir. 2022) (“We construe Title IX’s protections consistently with those of Title VII.”); Jennings v. Univ. of N.C., 482 F.3d 686, 695 (4th Cir. 2007) (“We look to case law interpreting Title VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 for guidance in evaluating a claim brought under Title IX.”); Pederson v. La. State Univ., 213 F.3d 858, 881 (5th Cir. 2000) (referencing Title VII standard for intent in defining intent under Title IX); Murray v. N.Y. Univ. Coll. of Dentistry, 57 F.3d 243, 249 (2d Cir. 1995) (“[I]n a Title IX suit for gender discrimination based on sexual harassment of a student, an educational institution may be held liable under standards similar to those applied in cases under Title VII.”); Lakoski v. James, 66 F.3d 751, 757–58 (5th Cir. 1995) (holding sex discrimination provisions in Title VII and Title IX are the same regarding employment discrimination); Roberts v. Colo. State Bd. of Agric., 998 F.2d 824, 832 (10th Cir. 1993) (explaining that although Title IX was explicitly modeled after Title VI, Title VII is “the most appropriate analogue” for determining what Title IX requires (quoting Mabry v. State Bd. of Cmty. Colls. & Occupational Educ., 813 F.2d 311, 316 n.6 (10th Cir. 1987))). This reliance appears to arise from the Supreme Court’s reference to Title VII standards when interpreting Title IX in the sexual harassment context even though the Court did not explicitly hold or state that Title VII standards apply.294See Davis v. Monroe Cnty. Bd. of Educ., 526 U.S. 629, 651 (1999) (citing two Supreme Court cases, Meritor Savings Bank, FSB v. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57, 67 (1986) and Oncale v. Sundower Offshore Services, Inc., 523 U.S. 75, 82 (1998), both of which resolved Title VII claims when defining parameters of actionable Title IX sex harassment); Franklin v. Gwinnett Cnty. Pub. Schs., 503 U.S. 60, 75 (1992) (stating that teacher-on-student sexual harassment constitutes discrimination on the basis of sex without explicitly referencing Title VII (citing Meritor Sav. Bank, FSB v. Vinson, 477 U.S. 57, 64 (1986) (finding that sexual harassment constitutes Title VII sex discrimination))); see also, e.g., Jennings, 482 F.3d at 695 (citing Davis, 526 U.S. at 651, and Franklin, 503 U.S. at 75, for the proposition that Title VII interpretation guides claims brought under Title IX); Rosa H. v. San Elizario Indep. Sch. Dist., 106 F.3d 648, 655 (5th Cir. 1997) (discussing reasons courts have read Franklin broadly to justify applying Title VII standards to Title IX claims). That said, the Supreme Court has recognized that Title VII and Title IX are not the same in all respects.295See Gebser v. Lago Vista Indep. Sch. Dist., 524 U.S. 274, 283–86 (1998) (observing that Title IX does not include a reference to an employer’s agents, unlike Title VII, and that Title IX is a condition on federal funds while Title VII is an outright, economy-wide prohibition). Other courts of appeals, while acknowledging that some Title VII standards might apply in the Title IX context, assert that Title VII principles do not always apply. For instance, the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit has treated Title VII’s and Title IX’s employment principles the same but declined to otherwise import Title VII standards into the Title IX context.296See Rosa H., 106 F.3d at 656 (retaining intentional discrimination requirement and explaining that “Franklin’s single citation to Meritor Savings . . . does not . . . justify the importation of other aspects of Title VII law”); Chance v. Rice Univ., 984 F.2d 151, 153 (5th Cir. 1993) (affirming district court’s application of Title VI rather than Title VII standards in Title IX context); see also Beasley v. St. Tammany Parish Sch. Bd., No. CIV.A. 96-2333, 1997 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 9844, at *9 (E.D. La. July 8, 1997) (noting that the Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit “does not blindly apply Title VII standards to the Title IX context”). The Court of Appeals for the Sixth Circuit also affirmed that Title VII principles do not “automatically apply.”297See Meriwether v. Hartop, 992 F.3d 492, 510 n.4 (6th Cir. 2021).. And the Courts of Appeals for the First and Ninth Circuits both have observed that a different analysis is required in athletics than in employment.298See Cohen v. Brown Univ., 101 F.3d 155, 177 (1st Cir. 1996) (stating that “[i]t is imperative to recognize” that employment and athletics require different analysis because “athletics presents a distinctly different situation”); Neal v. Bd. of Trs., 198 F.3d 763, 772 n.8 (9th Cir. 1999) (explaining that Title VII principles “are not relevant in the context of collegiate athletics” because “[u]nlike most employment settings, athletic teams are gender segregated”).

Declining to apply Title VII’s standards when interpreting Title IX makes sense. The statutory schemes are fundamentally different. Title VII states in part, “It shall be an unlawful employment practice for an employer . . . to fail or refuse to hire or to discharge any individual, or otherwise to discriminate against any individual with respect to his compensation, terms, conditions, or privileges of employment, because of such individual’s . . . sex.”29942 U.S.C. § 2000e-2(a). Unlike Title VII, which looks at the grounds for an employment decision, Title IX looks at the effect of treating a person differently on the basis of that person’s sex. And while Title IX permits distinguishing between the sexes in education programs and activities, Title VII never permits consideration of sex in employment decisions. Although both prohibit sex discrimination, each does so in a unique manner.

Title VII and Title IX also differ in another way. Although no court appears to have resolved the issue directly, courts implicitly recognize that Title IX prohibits denying a person equal opportunity because the person has a particular sex.300See supra Section II.A; see, e.g., Doe v. Columbia Coll. Chi., 933 F.3d 849, 856 (7th Cir. 2019) (finding that the plaintiff failed to allege denial of “an educational benefit because of his sex”); Tumminello v. Father Ryan High Sch., Inc., 678 Fed. App’x 281, 284 (6th Cir. 2017) (requiring a student to show—as proof of prima facie sexual harassment—that the harassment occurred “on the basis of his or her sex”); G.G. ex rel. Grimm v. Gloucester Cnty. Sch. Bd., 822 F.3d 709, 718 (4th Cir. 2016) (asking whether discrimination was based on “[the plaintiff’s] sex”), vacated and remanded on other grounds, 580 U.S. 1168 (2017). In contrast, the Court in Bostock concluded that Title VII liability is triggered if sex is considered even abstractly and without knowledge of a person’s exact sex.301Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1746 (2020) (“Any way you slice it, the employer intentionally refuses to hire applicants in part because of the affected individuals’ sex, even if it never learns any applicant’s sex.”). If a person is treated differently for having transgender status, under Bostock, that treatment constitutes sex discrimination under Title VII. But it does not under Title IX because transgender status only explains the relationship between a person’s gender identity and sex (that they differ). It does not say what the person’s sex is. Unlike in the Title VII context under Bostock, where a person can discriminate against someone on the basis of sex without knowing the person’s exact sex, in the Title IX context, such discrimination is not possible.

Bostock’s reasoning and holding cannot be unmoored from Title VII and attached to Title IX. To do so would be to fundamentally change how Title IX operates. If Title VII’s standards, as understood by Bostock, were fully imported, Title IX would prohibit any differential treatment except where expressly permitted—an effect which clashes directly with the text and early understandings.302See Section III.B (explaining that the text of Title IX and Congress’s approval of the 1975 regulations and 1979 Interpretation demonstrate that Title IX does not require sex-blind treatment). Indeed, the 1975 HEW regulations—which permit separating boys and girls into separate sports teams—would be upended, as they were adopted under only a congressional directive to issue rules concerning athletics and without explicit statutory exemptions for sex-based athletic programs. But as previously explained, Congress twice approved of those requirements—demonstrating that equal treatment, not sex blindness—is Title IX’s mandate. Applying Bostock to Title IX would change that.

Even the Grimm majority and Adams dissent did not go so far as to import Bostock wholesale into Title IX. They didn’t ask if sex was abstractly considered. Instead, they viewed the exclusion of Grimm and Adams from the bathroom each wanted to use as relevant to whether the schools violated Title IX. And both relied on Bostock’s but-for test solely to argue that sex was a but-for cause of the exclusion, and thus that the schools engaged in sex discrimination.

But therein lies the Grimm majority’s and Adams dissent’s error in relying upon Bostock. Not only did both fail to properly understand whether Grimm and Adams were similarly situated to students having a male sex, but they also imported a standard for when sex may never be considered into a circumstance in which no one disputed that it may be considered.303The U.S. Court of Appeals for the Seventh Circuit similarly erred in A.C. v. Metropolitan School District of Martinsville. 75 F.4th 760, 769 (7th Cir. 2023) (“Applying Bostock’s reasoning to Title IX, we have no trouble concluding that discrimination against transgender persons is sex discrimination for Title IX purposes, just as it is for Title VII purposes. As Bostock instructs, we ask whether our three plaintiffs are suffering negative consequences (for Title IX, lack of equal access to school programs) for behavior that is being tolerated in male students who are not transgender. Our decision in Whitaker followed this approach.” (citations omitted)). After all, Grimm and Adams were asking to be treated the same as biological males—not to abolish separate bathrooms.304That said, the effect of their request would be to abolish separate bathrooms as permitted by Title IX by changing the basis for the separation from sex to gender identity. And as the Adams majority points out, Title IX’s implementing regulations explicitly allow consideration of sex in the context of bathrooms.305See Adams ex rel. Kasper v. Sch. Bd. of St. Johns Cnty., 57 F.4th 791, 814 (11th Cir. 2022).

Even employing the but-for test as used in Bostock, however, to determine whether sex discrimination occurs when a school requires a student to use a restroom corresponding with the student’s sex, Adams remains correctly decided, and Grimm wrongly decided. When Title IX recognizes that sex is relevant for access to a physical space like a restroom, the question is whether the standard is applied equally to boys and girls—not whether sex is ever considered.306See supra Section III.B; see also Poloceno v. Dall. Indep. Sch. Dist., 826 Fed. App’x 359, 362 (5th Cir. 2020) (finding no disparate treatment where the standard was applied equally to boys and girls).

In the transgender context, any request for a federal-funding recipient to treat a person consistent with that person’s gender identity assumes that Title IX permits differential treatment in that circumstance. After all, a person with a female gender identity would likely not want to be treated like a male. Treating a person consistent with a gender identity of “female” means to treat that person as that person believes a female should be treated—such as referring to that person by female rather than male pronouns.307See, e.g., Yogyakarta Principles, supra note 14, at 6 n.2 (“Gender identity . . . refer[s] to each person’s deeply felt internal and individual experience of gender . . . including the personal sense of the body (which may involve, if freely chosen, modification of bodily appearance or function by medical, surgical, or other means) and other expressions of gender, including dress, speech and mannerisms.”). If a request for such treatment arises in the Title IX context, the request is an implicit assumption that Title IX permits such differential treatment. After all, if Title IX did not permit such treatment, the past five decades of teachers using different pronouns in accord with English grammar to refer to male and female students was illegal.

To set up the but-for test as the Court used it in Bostock, imagine that two students are similar in every respect except their sexes. One is a biological male who identifies as a female (like Whitaker, Grimm, and Adams), the other is a biological female who identifies as a female. Again, Title IX concerns itself with whether the person experienced discrimination on the basis of sex as understood when Title IX was adopted—not on the basis of sex and gender as understood today. And even Bostock set up the test under Title VII by comparing two individuals with different sexes. Unlike in Bostock, where one suffers an adverse employment action and the other does not, here, both are given access to a restroom corresponding with their respective biological sexes (and maybe also are given access to unisex bathrooms). No matter the sex, the rule applies the same.

As an additional matter, Bostock and Adams reveal why Whitaker’s sex-stereotype theory also fails. Neither Bostock nor Price Waterhouse made sex stereotypes anything more than evidence of disparate treatment. Indeed, Bostock focused on whether discrimination on the basis of a given trait involved consideration of sex.308See Bostock v. Clayton Cnty., 140 S. Ct. 1731, 1737 (2020). And Price Waterhouse emphasized that a stereotype is a view that certain traits should or should not exist in conjunction with a given sex. Treating “sex” as a stereotype inverts the analysis.309See Adams, 57 F.4th at 813 (observing that “‘sex’ is not a stereotype”). After all, the purpose of examining acts based on stereotypes is to determine whether the act was really based on sex—not whether discrimination on the basis of sex veils discrimination on the basis of something else. Contrary to what Whitaker held, doing what Title IX explicitly says is permitted—separating private facilities on the basis of sex—is far from acting on stereotypes. The separation is based on sex itself without regard to any other traits, and it treats each sex equally by imposing the same standard on both sexes.

V.      Title IX, the Affordable Care Act, and Federally Funded Medical Programs

A.      Title IX’s Incorporation into Section 1557 of the Affordable Care Act and Subsequent Interpretations

In 2010, Congress passed the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act (“Affordable Care Act” or “ACA”), which extended Title IX’s requirements to cover federally funded medical programs.310Patient Protection & Affordable Care Act, Pub. L. No. 111-148, tit. I, § 1557, 124 Stat. 260 (2010) (codified at 42 U.S.C. § 18116); see also Walker v. Azar, 480 F. Supp. 3d 417, 420–21 (E.D.N.Y. 2020) (recounting the history of the ACA and the Department of Health and Human Services’ interpretation). Section 1557 of the Act prohibits discrimination “on the ground prohibited under” several federal statutes, including Title IX, in “any health program or activity.”31142 U.S.C. § 18116(a). The ACA further incorporated Title IX’s nondiscrimination requirements by providing “[t]he enforcement mechanisms provided for and available under . . . title IX” for addressing violations of Section 1557.312Id.; see also Walker, 480 F. Supp. 3d at 420. Section 1557 also delegated authority to the Secretary of Health and Human Services (“HHS”) to create implementing regulations.31342 U.S.C. § 18116(c).

Each of HHS’s attempts to interpret Section 1557 in the transgender context were struck down, however.314See Neese v. Becerra, 640 F. Supp. 3d 668, 687 (N.D. Tex. 2022) (granting declaratory relief); Walker, 480 F. Supp. 3d at 420; Whitman-Walker Clinic, Inc. v. U.S. Dep’t of Health and Hum. Servs., 485 F. Supp. 3d 1, 64 (D.D.C. 2020) (granticing injunctive relief); Franciscan All., Inc. v. Burwell, 227 F. Supp. 3d 660, 696 (N.D. Tex. 2016) (granting injunctive relief). In 2016, HHS issued a series of rules (“2016 Rules”) explaining Section 1557’s nondiscrimination requirement. The rules restated that the ACA prohibits discrimination “on the basis of . . . sex,” among other classifications.315Walker, 480 F. Supp. 3d at 420–21 (quoting Nondiscrimination in Health Programs and Activities, 80 Fed. Reg. 54172, 54218 (Sept. 8, 2015) (codified as amended at 45 C.F.R. § 92.2)). The rules then explained that “on the basis of sex” includes “on the basis of . . . sex stereotyping[ ] or gender identity.”316Id. (quoting Nondiscrimination in Health Programs and Activities, 80 Fed. Reg. at 54216). HHS defined “sex stereotyping” as “stereotypical notions of gender, including expectations of how any individual represents or communicates gender to others, such as behavior, clothing, hairstyles, activities, voice, mannerisms, or body characteristics.”317Id. at 421 (quoting Nondiscrimination in Health Programs and Activities, 80 Fed. Reg. at 54216–17 (emphasis added)). And it defined “gender identity” as “an individual’s internal sense of gender, which may be different from that individual’s sex assigned at birth.”318Id. (quoting Nondiscrimination in Health Programs and Activities, 80 Fed. Reg. at 54216). HHS argued that its reading of Title IX was consistent with existing nondiscrimination law as well as “agencies’ and courts’ interpretations that discrimination on the basis of sex includes discrimination on the basis of gender identity.”319Id. (quoting Nondiscrimination in Health Programs and Activities, 81 Fed. Reg. 31376, 31388 (May 18, 2016)).

This interpretation was enjoined in December 2016.320See Franciscan All., Inc. v. Burwell, 227 F. Supp. 3d 660, 669–70 (N.D. Tex. 2016). In June 2019, HHS gave notice that it was withdrawing the 2016 Rules’ “novel definition of ‘sex’” to make the regulation “more consistent” with other agencies’ Title IX regulations.321Walker, 480 F. Supp. 3d at 422 (quoting Nondiscrimination in Health and Health Education Programs or Activities, 84 Fed. Reg. 27846, 27856 (June 14, 2019)). And a year later, HHS issued revised rules (“2020 Rules”).322See Nondiscrimination in Health and Health Education Programs or Activities, Delegation of Authority, 85 Fed. Reg. 37160 (June 19, 2020). Unlike the 2016 Rules, the 2020 Rules did not define “sex” and instead merely referenced Title IX.323See id. at 37244. The preamble went further, declaring that the withdrawal was based on a different reading of Title IX.324Walker, 480 F. Supp. 3d at 422–23 (citing Nondiscrimination in Health and Health Education Programs or Activities, Delegation of Authority, 85 Fed. Reg. at 37175–94) (reciting statements in the preamble that conflict with the 2016 Rules). It emphasized that “sex” should be understood to refer to a “biological binary of male and female”; that Title IX adopted this understanding; that distinctions based on sex—a biological binary—are permissible and sometimes necessary; and that no agency had previously accepted the 2016 Rules’ understanding of sex and gender identity.325Id. (quoting Nondiscrimination in Health and Health Education Programs or Activities, Delegation of Authority, 85 Fed. Reg. at 37178). Recognizing pending litigation and that the Supreme Court had not yet interpreted “sex” in Title VII, HHS noted that its elimination of the definition of “sex” “would not preclude application of” judicial construction.326Id. at 422 (quoting Nondiscrimination in Health and Health Education Programs or Activities, Delegation of Authority, 85 Fed. Reg. at 37168). The 2020 Rules, like the prior 2016 Rules, were subsequently enjoined in legal challenges.327See id. at 420, 429; see also Whitman-Walker Clinic, Inc. v. U.S. Dep’t of Health and Hum. Servs., 485 F. Supp. 3d 1, 10, 64 (D.D.C. 2020)..

HHS reversed its stance yet again in May 2021.328Am. Coll. of Pediatricians v. Becerra, No. 21-cv-195, 2022 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 209569, at *15 (E.D. Tenn. Nov. 18, 2022) (citing Notification of Interpretation and Enforcement of Section 1557 of the Affordable Care Act and Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, 86 Fed. Reg. 27984, 27984 (May 25, 2021)). In its “Notification of Interpretation and Enforcement” (“2021 Notification”), HHS stated its intent to apply Bostock v. Clayton County to Section 1557.329Id. (citing Notification of Interpretation and Enforcement of Section 1557 of the Affordable Care Act and Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, 86 Fed. Reg. at 27984).. HHS would read Section 1557 to prohibit discrimination “on the basis of gender identity.”330Id. (quoting Notification of Interpretation and Enforcement of Section 1557 of the Affordable Care Act and Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, 86 Fed. Reg. at 27984). This interpretation was struck down, too.331See Neese v. Becerra, 640 F. Supp. 3d 668, 687 (N.D. Tex. 2022) (granting declaratory relief). But in July 2023, again citing Bostock, HHS issued a notice of proposed rulemaking which would interpret “13 HHS authorities that prohibit discrimination on the basis of sex”—including Section 1557—to also prohibit discrimination on the basis of gender identity.332See Health and Human Services Grants Regulation, 88 Fed. Reg. 44750, 44753 (proposed July 13, 2023) (to be codified at 45 C.F.R. pt. 75).

B.      Applying the Original Understanding of Title IX to Section 1557

Section 1557 uses almost identical language as Title IX, stating that “an individual shall not, on the ground prohibited under . . . title IX . . . be excluded from participation in, be denied the benefits of, or be subjected to discrimination under, any health program or activity.”33342 U.S.C. § 18116 (emphasis added); see 20 U.S.C. § 1681(a). HHS’s 2020 Rules correctly understood that by incorporating Title IX, Section 1557 incorporated the original understanding of “sex” in Title IX. Indeed, as explained above, Bostock does not compel reading “sex” in Title IX to mean anything different than what it originally meant. HHS’s attempts to rely on Bostock to add gender identity to the traits protected by Section 1557 is thus unfounded.

But more than that, Section 1557 incorporated what Title IX said about sex.334See, e.g., Franciscan All., Inc. v. Burwell, 227 F. Supp. 3d 660, 686 (N.D. Tex. 2016) (“Section 1557 clearly incorporates Title IX’s prohibition of sex discrimination.”); Whitman-Walker Clinic, Inc. v. U.S. Dep’t of Health and Hum. Servs., 485 F. Supp. 3d 1, 12 (“By outlawing discrimination ‘on the ground prohibited’ by Title IX, Section 1557 bars discrimination ‘on the basis of sex.’” (quoting 20 U.S.C. § 1681(a))). Consequently, Section 1557 mandates equal treatment, not sex blindness or identical treatment. Indeed, if it did require sex blindness, the statute would ignore the numerous circumstances when medical treatment should account for whether a person is male or female.335See, e.g., Vera Regitz-Zagrosek, Sex and Gender Differences in Health, 13 Sci. & Soc’y 596, 596 (2012) (observing “important biological and behavioural differences” that “affect manifestation, epidemiology and pathophysiology of many widespread diseases and the approach to health care”). And just like under Title IX, if no disparate treatment occurs on the basis of sex, no discrimination occurs. After all, because Section 1557 incorporates the standard from Title IX’s statutory language, it only prohibits disparate treatment, not disparate impact.

To illustrate the effect of this understanding of Section 1557, consider an insurance provider that offers coverage for mastectomies. With an advance apology for the candor necessary for the analysis, insurance coverage for mastectomies provides a unique test case because both men and women can undergo the procedure.336See Surgery for Breast Cancer in Men, Am. Cancer Soc’y, https://perma.cc/KQ72-RDE3; see also Mastectomy, Mayo Clinic, https://perma.cc/JU8Q-XSCW; Enlarged Breasts in Men (Gynecomastia), Mayo Clinic, https://perma.cc/84HZ-ZH3P. And unlike in Adams, where an explicit carve-out permitted separate bathrooms on the basis of sex, here, no carve-out exists for mastectomies. Returning to the hypothetical, one mastectomy the insurance provider covers is for gynecomastia, a condition where a biological male develops excess breast tissue.337Gynecomastia occurs when a biological male’s body experiences an imbalance of estrogen and testosterone, causing an increase of breast tissue. See Enlarged Breasts in Men (Gynecomastia), supra note 336. But it refuses coverage if the purpose of the surgery is to make a biological female appear physically like a male, and the breast tissue is otherwise physically healthy and naturally developing (or has naturally developed). These two surgeries are not identical—one is to remove tissue that developed because of an abnormality, the other to remove tissue that developed naturally but is now undesirable because of how the biological female identifies.338At puberty, a biological male’s breasts cease to develop any further absent a biological irregularity such as gynecomastia, while a biological female’s will continue to develop naturally. See, e.g., Asma Javed & Aida Lteif, Development of the Human Breast, 27 Seminars Plastic Surgery 5, 5, 11 (2013); Normal Breast Development and Changes, Johns Hopkins Med., http://perma.cc/WT2M-U7XG.. Even if the biological male wants the breast tissue removed because of psychological discomfort, his discomfort arises from fact that the male body does not naturally develop this excess tissue.339See Enlarged Breasts in Men (Gynecomastia), supra note 336. In contrast, a woman who now identifies as male—or something else—and wants the tissue removed no longer desires to have naturally developed female breasts. The denial of coverage is rooted in whether the breast tissue developed in the course of normal biological development and is physically healthy. Coverage depends solely on the reason for the surgery.

At least one court, however, has concluded that a denial of coverage for surgeries to make a person’s physical traits align with that person’s gender identity violates Section 1557.340C.P. v. Blue Cross Blue Shield, No. 20-cv-06145, 2022 U.S. Dist. LEXIS 227832, at *1 (W.D. Wash. Dec. 19, 2022). Applying Bostock, it reasoned that Section 1557 prohibits sex discrimination based on transgender status.341Id. at *6. In March 2022, the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit also concluded in a similar case, without reaching the merits, that Bostock applies to Section 1557 because in its view, Title IX’s and Title VII’s protections are similar. See Doe v. Snyder, 28 F.4th 103, 112–14 (9th Cir. 2022). Moreover, the court reasoned, considering that a person has gender dysphoria requires referring to sex.342Blue Cross, 2022 U.S. Dist. LEXIS, at *16. And a person who has gender dysphoria “cannot” but identify as transgender.343Id. Thus, the court held, the denial of coverage is on the basis of transgender status and is unlawful sex discrimination under Section 1557.344Id.

That is incorrect, as well as confusing. As explained above, Bostock cannot be applied to Title IX. And so it cannot be applied to Section 1557 either. Even if Bostock were applied, the insurance provider in the hypothetical would not violate Section 1557. Two things are in play—sex and the nature of the surgery. And a male who has abnormally enlarged breasts, identifies as a male, and seeks surgical removal of his excess breast tissue and a woman who has naturally developed breasts, identifies as a male, and seeks surgical removal of her breast tissue are dissimilar in three ways: their sexes, the conditions of their breasts (natural versus abnormal development), and their reasons for seeking a mastectomy. For that reason, the Bostock framework is inapplicable here.

Even if the hypothetical is reframed and squeezed into Bostock’s framework, the outcome remains the same. Imagine that the provider provides coverage for all surgeries except for what it deems as “transition surgeries”—surgeries that alter a person’s physical traits to align with that person’s gender identity. A biological man wants a transition surgery to appear as a woman, and a biological woman wants a transition surgery to appear as a man. The surgeries for each would be different—after all, the biological man wants to look like a woman while the biological woman wants to look like a man. Each seeks to remove or add different organs and body parts. And so there are still three differences in the comparison analysis: (1) the purpose of the surgery, (2) the type of surgery involved, and (3) the person’s sex. But assuming for the sake of argument that the reason for and nature of the surgery are classified the same (alignment of one’s physical traits with one’s gender identity), coverage is denied regardless of sex. The denial turns on the reason for the procedure, not the person’s sex. Because both sexes are denied coverage, no sex discrimination occurs under Section 1557—even if Bostock’s but-for test is applied. 345Providing coverage for intersex surgeries but not for transition surgeries would not alter this conclusion. As explained above, surgeries to address intersex conditions seek to increase the harmony between a person’s body and the person’s sex. Such surgeries are fundamentally different than a surgery that seeks to reduce that harmony by altering a person’s body away from that person’s sex and into conformity with how a person seeks to express a particular gender identity.

It could be argued that the real basis for the denial of coverage is the view that a person’s physical traits must correspond with a person’s sex. And so, the argument might conclude, the insurance provider is impermissibly denying coverage based on sex. Again, however, Title IX is concerned with equal opportunity. Unlike Title VII, Title IX does not forbid ever accounting for a person’s sex. When a rule is applied equally to the sexes, no violation of Title IX occurs—even if the rule involves consideration of a person’s sex. That’s why, after all, the 1975 HEW sports regulations and 1979 interpretation were acceptable under Title IX without a statutory exemption to Title IX’s nondiscrimination requirement. Here, if the insurance provider offers coverage unless the treatment or surgery reduces the alignment of the person’s body with that person’s sex, the rule applies regardless of whether a person has a male or female sex. To be sure, sex is not entirely out of the picture. But, again, the test under Title IX and thus under Section 1557 is not whether sex was considered at all. Under Bostock’s but-for test, no sex discrimination has occured.

In sum, Section 1557 permits treating a person as a male or female based on that person’s biological sex. And it does not compel providing insurance coverage for medical treatments that reshape a person’s body away from alignment with that person’s sex and into conformity with how a person seeks to express a particular gender. Under that same reasoning, it does not require providing the actual surgeries or treatments either. An interpretation to the contrary—such as in HHS’s 2016 Rules, 2021 Notification, or 2023 proposed changes to its grants regulation—is without basis in law.

Conclusion

Title IX was adopted to ensure that women receive equal educational opportunities as men. It embodied the view that although women and men have immutable, biological differences, those differences should not disqualify a woman from pursuing her dreams. And it reflects the common understanding at the time of its adoption that a woman is a woman because of her sex, which is immutable. Consequently, equality based on gender identity is not the equality that Title IX promises or was created to deliver. Title IX forbids only discrimination based on sex, not discrimination based on gender identity or transgender status. Treating a person as male or female based on that person’s sex does not run afoul of that protection.

Share this article

Twitter
Facebook
LinkedIn